Tania Lombrozo on What Explanations Are

Tania Lombrozo on What Explanations Are

Released Monday, 16th January 2023
 1 person rated this episode
Tania Lombrozo on What Explanations Are

Tania Lombrozo on What Explanations Are

Tania Lombrozo on What Explanations Are

Tania Lombrozo on What Explanations Are

Monday, 16th January 2023
 1 person rated this episode
Rate Episode

Episode Transcript

Transcripts are displayed as originally observed. Some content, including advertisements may have changed.

Use Ctrl + F to search

0:00

The

0:00

first step in taking care of your body

0:02

and your mind begins with eating and drinking

0:05

right every day. And what better way

0:07

to do that than with delicious palm wonderful

0:09

one hundred percent pomegranate juice.

0:12

Palm wonderful pomegranate juice is

0:14

whole pressed with no added sugar,

0:16

no preservatives, and no fillers. It

0:18

comes with seven hundred milligrams of polyphenol

0:21

antioxidants per a down serving and

0:23

has as much potassium as a banana.

0:25

Palm wonderful tastes great right out of the

0:27

bottle or as an ingredient in all sorts

0:30

of delicious drinks. Drink it daily,

0:32

feel it forever. To find delicious recipes

0:34

and learn more about palm, visit

0:36

palm wonderful dot com.

0:40

Hello, everyone, and welcome to the Mindscape podcast.

0:42

I'm your host, Sean Carroll's. very

0:44

natural when things go wrong, when

0:46

when something is very different than what you were

0:49

led to expect it would be, to

0:51

demand an explanation. To

0:53

ask why is it like this?

0:55

What is the reason why the explanation

0:58

for the state of affairs that you didn't expect?

1:01

But what does that mean? Exactly. Does

1:03

an explanation mean some connection

1:06

between one event or another? Or is it

1:08

a way that the world is. If

1:11

you remember back when we talked to Judea Pearl

1:13

about cause and effect, and

1:15

Pearl of course is one of the world's experts

1:17

in teasing out what

1:19

causes lead to what effects in all

1:21

sorts of messy situations in the

1:23

real world. He claimed

1:26

that babies spend their

1:28

time making causal maps of the world

1:30

saying if I poke this, it reacts

1:32

in this other way. So what

1:34

exactly is going on? Not just in babies,

1:37

but in grown ups also when we human

1:39

beings construct this

1:41

image of the world or this model

1:43

of the world, which says this

1:45

is an explanation for this other

1:47

thing over there. Well, today's guest is

1:49

Tania She's one of the world's experts

1:51

in exactly this question. She's

1:54

a psychologist at Princeton University

1:56

and her lab at Princeton is called

1:58

the Concepts and Cognition Lab,

2:00

which I love that as a name. I would love to

2:02

work in the concepts and cognition lab

2:05

where she studies what an explanation

2:08

is, what do we mean when

2:10

we say, here's the explanation for

2:12

that. What do we what should we mean?

2:15

What are we talking about philosophically as

2:17

well as psychologically? Do

2:19

people agree? On what explanations

2:21

are Why do we want them? What

2:23

what is it psychologically that

2:25

moves us to burst into

2:27

the room and demand an explanation? For

2:30

something. I like it because

2:32

it's not only a psychology topic,

2:34

but of course, it has something to do with

2:36

the structure of the world out there.

2:39

The fact that there are things in the world

2:41

that we accept as explanations.

2:43

This is an interesting fact all by itself and

2:45

there's other things that someone might say you

2:47

demand an explanation, which most of us would go,

2:50

no, that doesn't really work. Going

2:53

down to very, you detailed

2:55

questions at their, for example,

2:57

at the intersection of science and religion.

3:00

When you say, why is there something rather

3:02

than nothing? And someone says, well, God

3:04

made it that way. Is that a

3:06

good explanation? Does that satisfy

3:08

you? Should it satisfy you? And I'm not

3:10

telling you what the answer is. I'm saying these are very

3:12

good questions. We're gonna get into it,

3:14

so let's go. Donie

3:33

welcome to the Mindscape Podcast. Thanks for

3:36

having, Nishan. So you work on

3:38

explanations, which is

3:40

something that to me sounds like very natural

3:42

for a psychologist to work on. You know,

3:44

I it's always funny to me when I read

3:46

psychology papers and they say, like,

3:48

this is actually an understudied area of

3:51

psychology. And I I think that yours is

3:53

one. Is it true that explanation is an under

3:55

studied area of cognitive psychology? I

3:57

think it depends which types of explanations

4:00

you're thinking about. So two communities

4:02

have thought about explanation for a long time. One

4:04

is, social psychologists. They've been really interested in

4:06

how we explain our own behavior and other people's behavior.

4:08

And there's decades of research specifically

4:11

thinking about explanation in that context. And

4:13

another community that's been really focused on

4:15

explanation is educators, people thinking about

4:17

educational psychology and learning. An

4:19

explanation in those context. I think

4:21

what's newer is people

4:24

appreciating how fundamental

4:26

explanation might be to our everyday cognitive

4:28

lives. Not just in the social

4:30

domain, but more generally. So

4:32

I and many other people as well, I

4:34

think over the last, I think, two, three

4:36

decades have really focused

4:39

on new questions related to explanation,

4:42

but drawing upon what we know from social psychology and

4:44

educational psychology. And so but do you

4:46

sure work then in the in the domain of cognitive

4:48

psychology? I consider myself a cognitive

4:50

psychologist, although, but, you know, as with any

4:52

demarcations between disciplines, the boundaries

4:55

get a little bit fuzzy and I -- Right. -- I think they

4:57

should not be very well sharply

4:59

drawn. And I think what's most distinctive

5:01

about the approach that I've taken to thinking

5:03

about explanation is that many of the questions

5:05

I've interested in are the ones that arise in the context

5:07

of philosophers of science have

5:09

been interested in explanation for a very long time.

5:11

Overwhelmingly thinking about the role of explanation

5:13

and science, but not exclusively. And

5:15

I think if you take

5:18

seriously the idea that there is some important

5:20

connections between everyday human cognition

5:22

and what we do is everyday research trying to make

5:24

sense of the world and what scientists are

5:26

doing in their quest to make sense of the world

5:28

then it's very natural to think that the kinds of questions

5:30

that arise about explanation in the context of

5:32

science and philosophers of science have been interested in

5:34

also have analogues in the context of just

5:36

everyday human cognition. I did wanna ask you about

5:38

that because I I can imagine the

5:40

philosophers want to know what

5:42

explanation is and, you know,

5:44

what's a good explanation, whatever, whereas I

5:46

might imagine psychologists are also interested

5:48

in how we do

5:51

explanations, how we start doing explanations

5:53

as children and things like that? So do you see

5:55

quite a bit of overlap and intersection

5:57

there? I think that's right. So

6:00

I think philosophers have asked largely

6:02

what explanation is and also what

6:04

explanations should be. So asking a more

6:06

normative question. I think those questions

6:08

are also relevant for psychology. But

6:10

on top of that, we might want to think about

6:12

where explanations come from developmentally. Mhmm.

6:14

But also one of the things that I've asked a

6:16

lot in my own homework is, what do

6:18

explanations do? And I

6:20

think that might be a more useful

6:23

entry point for starting to think about this. Right? So rather

6:25

first defining what an explanation is, and

6:27

then maybe thinking about its consequences, we

6:29

can ask, what do explanations do for

6:31

us? Why are we the sorts of creatures who explain?

6:33

Right. What's the function of this activity?

6:35

And perhaps by getting a grip on that,

6:37

on the role of explanation and what explanations do, we

6:39

can then work backwards to thinking about what explanations

6:42

are. Right? So rather than starting from a

6:44

definition sort of starting from a functional

6:46

role? Howard Bauchner:

6:48

And as if I recall correctly, there's

6:51

even the possibility that much

6:54

is in physics, you could get

6:56

feedback from the science end

6:58

into philosophy, and I think that in one of your

7:00

papers, you're saying that this philosopher

7:02

made the following claims about our intuitions, about

7:04

explanations. So we tested them, and

7:06

it turns out those not our intuitions. Yeah,

7:09

that's right. And we've done that across

7:11

a variety of projects and sometimes we find that our

7:13

results accord very closely

7:15

to what further said, and sometimes we find interesting

7:18

departures. And, of course, whenever that happens, there's an

7:20

interesting question. Is it just that humans

7:22

are wrong or the philosophers are

7:24

wrong? I think it varies

7:26

case by case. Do the philosophers then

7:28

listen? Are they are they do

7:30

you is it an active in practice

7:33

back and forth between your work and those of the

7:35

philosophers? That's an interesting question. I think it

7:37

it really varies by what question

7:39

philosophers are asking and, of course,

7:41

switch philosophers a huge variability

7:43

in the field as I'm sure you know better

7:45

than I do in the extent to which

7:47

people engage with empirical work of various kinds

7:50

and philosophical work. But I think I think it does

7:52

vary. I can give you an

7:54

example if you'd like an thesis where I think

7:56

there is interesting cross

7:58

talk back and forth. So one

8:01

area where isymologists in

8:03

particular have been really interested in explanation is

8:05

in the context of what's called inference the best

8:07

explanation. And this is something that I

8:09

think most people kind of intuitively are familiar

8:11

with, you know, Sherlock Holmes claimed that

8:13

he engaged in deduction, but a lot of the time when

8:15

he was used to really inference the best explanation. He

8:17

was looking at a bunch of evidence

8:19

and trying to come up with it would best explain

8:22

that body of evidence and on the

8:24

basis of that concluding that explanation might

8:26

be true. So that's a pattern of inference that

8:28

we see in science, but we see all the time just

8:30

everyday cognition. And one

8:33

question might be, when

8:35

we to engage in this kind of reasoning.

8:37

Right? Is it ever normative

8:39

warranted? Is it a good kind of reasoning or is

8:41

it a mistake? And I think there's

8:43

truth to both of those things. There's conditions under which

8:45

it's good and conditions under which it's bad. But there's an

8:47

interesting dialogue that's happened back and forth

8:49

between some of the empirical evidence and some of the

8:51

kinds of normative claims that small just might make,

8:53

but have to do with thinking about what the

8:55

goals of that kind of inference might

8:57

be. So you might think our goal

8:59

in engaging in

9:01

certain kinds of inference like it's like this might just

9:03

be to be, like, as accurate as possible --

9:05

Yep. -- meaning that we want to sort

9:07

of, like, minimize our long term inaccurate

9:09

see. We just want to, like, in the long run, get things right,

9:11

and we Tania have practices for updating our

9:14

beliefs. That mean that we're gonna in the long range

9:16

be least raw. And if you have

9:18

that view, you might think that what we ought to do is

9:20

something like play what's called base rule, base

9:22

in inference from statistics. It's sort of a

9:24

rule that tells us how to combine our prior

9:26

beliefs. With the evidence we have in order to arrive at what they

9:28

call a posterior probability. Now it

9:30

turns out that if you look at human

9:33

explanation, evaluation, and so on, and these

9:35

processes adverts the best explanation, there's

9:37

some systematic departures from what bayes rule

9:39

tells us that we should do. No. Yeah.

9:42

I know. I know. I'm sorry. I'm sorry to be the bearer

9:45

of bad news for somebody who

9:47

wants to add things. But

9:50

and I'm happy to say more about what those look

9:52

like, but the interesting thing is, you know, so

9:54

philosophers could just say, well, I

9:56

guess, you know, lay people are are just wrong

9:58

about this. They're doing poorly. But I think

10:00

a really interesting idea that's that's what

10:02

proposed is maybe maybe the thing humans

10:04

are trying to optimize isn't long term

10:06

inaccuracy, maybe it's something else.

10:08

So what might add something else be? What might something

10:10

that has I guess that's just what I was gonna

10:12

ask, you know, human

10:14

beings evolve under evolution, natural

10:16

selection, you know, reproductive fitness and

10:18

things like that. So in some sense,

10:20

the answer is always reproductive

10:22

fitness. Right? But I could

10:24

imagine that having an accurate

10:27

and predictive model of reality

10:29

helps with my reproductive fitness. Right? Yeah,

10:32

that's right. So the one

10:34

of the proposals and there's a handful of people

10:36

who've argued for this under the banner of

10:38

exploitationism, is that what we want to do is

10:40

get things mostly right in the short

10:42

term rather than being least

10:45

wrong in the long term. And

10:47

that's something that I think you can imagine trying to

10:49

motivate in terms of reproductive fitness.

10:51

Yeah. Right? We don't we don't know if we're gonna be

10:53

around long term. But if

10:55

we can get things mostly right in the short

10:57

term, that might be that might be the standard

10:59

that actually matters. And it turns out

11:01

that if that's what you're going for, you

11:03

shouldn't always use space roll. Sometimes you should do

11:05

something a little bit different. You might

11:07

also think that what we ought to do

11:09

depends on our cognitive limitations is humans. Right? If

11:11

we just don't have the the cognitive

11:13

capacities, that allow us to

11:15

engage in certain kinds of statistical

11:17

inferences or very complicated kinds of

11:19

mental computations. You might think that we ought

11:21

to employ the kinds of shortcuts that

11:23

are gonna be good enough given the

11:25

cognitive machinery that we have. And so that's another

11:27

idea that I think again makes sense within an

11:29

evolutionary context. But gives

11:31

us goals for what we're trying to do that look a

11:33

little bit different from, for

11:35

example, just applying basic inference. Yeah, I

11:37

mean, thinking and being cognitive Carroll's. Both

11:39

takes a lot of energy and a lot

11:41

of space, I guess, a lot of neurons, but

11:43

also time. And maybe you don't have time when

11:45

the lion is bearing down on you to think too

11:47

hard about what to do next. That's right. That's right.

11:50

And so being fast, being efficient, having

11:52

sort of heuristics or mental shortcuts arriving

11:54

at conclusions might be very beneficial. And

11:56

that's some of what we In terms of the explanations

11:58

we prefer. Right? So for example, one of the things

12:00

that we've looked at in my lab is people's

12:02

preference for similar explanations. And

12:05

you might imagine simpler explanations

12:07

are easier to process, easier to

12:09

remember, easier to arrive at and so and

12:11

so you might see a host of these benefits. So

12:13

I I was going to ask, and maybe that's

12:15

the answer. What what are the systematic

12:17

deviations from sort of perfect bayesian reasoning

12:19

that we might expect in real human Right? So there've

12:21

been a handful, and I'll tell you just a couple for

12:23

which we have the most evidence. Mhmm. So

12:25

one of them is that there is some evidence

12:27

that people seem to be more

12:29

sensitive to the

12:32

evidence that they ought to

12:34

compared to patient inference, meaning that

12:36

they will converge to an explanation that

12:38

fits the data well more,

12:40

you know, more quickly than they should and

12:42

consistent with this idea that they're trying to get to the it's

12:44

probably right fast. Interesting.

12:46

Okay. In my own lab,

12:48

one of the things that we have looked it as I mentioned to

12:50

simplicity. And the way we've

12:53

we've tried to get at that in psychology experiments

12:55

is by giving people scenarios where there

12:57

is a winner a couple of effects that they

12:59

observe and they're trying to come up with the best causal

13:01

explanation. So they're trying to come up with explanation that

13:03

sites one or more causes that

13:05

generate those effects. And under those

13:07

conditions, if you know the probability of

13:09

the causes and you know the probability of the effects,

13:11

given the causes, you could just

13:13

do the math. And so in some sense, we kind of

13:15

have the ground truth

13:17

for what the right pattern of reasoning

13:19

would be if people were just doing was most

13:21

likely. But what we find is that although people are

13:23

very sensitive to the probabilistic evidence,

13:25

they choose simpler explanations more often

13:27

than they should, where we define simpler explanations

13:29

as those involve fewer causes that

13:31

are themselves. So, you know, for example, if

13:33

you have two symptoms that you can explain by appeal

13:35

to one disease or by appeal to two

13:37

diseases that each does cause one symptom, you

13:39

find that people prefer the single disease explanation

13:42

more often than they ought

13:44

to given the probabilistic

13:46

evidence that they have. Physicists certainly act that way,

13:48

but maybe it works in physics in a way that it might

13:50

not work in medicine or everyday life. Yeah, it's

13:52

an interesting idea. You know,

13:54

in our in our lab cases, we

13:57

know what the ground truth is. Right? So we set

13:59

things up so that we we have some basis for

14:01

saying what the what's most likely or what's

14:03

not. But in most real world

14:05

cases, we don't have the

14:07

ability to cleanly say when people are

14:09

getting things right and when they're getting things

14:11

wrong. And so what we could be seeing in

14:13

the lab is the overgeneralization of

14:15

a strategy that actually maybe does make a

14:17

lot of sense in a lot of real world cases. I mean,

14:19

in the physics cases, and I'd be curious

14:21

if you have a a thought

14:23

on our physicists' right to be doing this. Have they

14:25

gotten to be doing this? Has it helped

14:27

scientific practice of theorizing for

14:29

them to show a preference for explanations that have this

14:31

kind of structure? I think

14:33

is a is a big ongoing debate to be

14:35

perfectly honest, especially in in my

14:37

little corner of fundamental physics, where

14:40

progress is a little stalled these days.

14:42

And so people are debating

14:44

different methodologies based on their

14:46

personal preferences. Right? And, you

14:48

know, some like like I have a

14:50

strategy which is to step back and think about

14:52

the foundations in a more philosophical way

14:54

to make sure that, you know, we're on a firm

14:56

ground where we where we do

14:58

our further down the road

15:00

reasoning. Other people are just

15:02

gonna, like, switch fields and, you

15:04

know, come to some area where they can

15:06

come up with a better explanation, test against the

15:08

data, and others are gonna argue about

15:10

beauty and math and all these things.

15:12

So I I that's why I was asking you. I real

15:14

I It's -- Yeah. -- physicists love

15:16

what works. Right? And when

15:18

some strategy works for one problem, they declare

15:21

victory, but the next problem is always

15:23

different, so we don't know. Yeah. Yeah. And I

15:25

think the everyday cognition cases are hard. If if I had

15:27

to guess, I would say that there

15:29

are many cases where preference for explanations

15:31

for the structure, in fact, does lead us so

15:33

sorry. Right. And That's that's the guess. I think

15:35

it's very hard to quantify that in in everyday

15:38

cases. Well, as a psychologist, is there

15:40

is there an understanding of psychologically

15:43

why we are driven to seek

15:45

explanations? You know, is

15:47

there is it just that there's a part of a

15:49

human brain that is naturally curious?

15:51

Or which sounds

15:53

kind of lofty almost

15:55

like we're naturally curious creatures or is

15:58

it is it more down to earth do you think? So,

16:00

we definitely have evidence that

16:02

basically from the moment kids

16:04

have the language capacities to ask

16:06

questions, they are asking

16:08

questions. And a lot of those

16:10

questions are what I would call explanation seeking

16:12

questions. So

16:15

it seems like it's an

16:17

early emerging and capacity, and we know it

16:19

plays an important role in human learning.

16:21

So what I've argued in some of my work, and I

16:23

think other people have argued for things along

16:25

similar is that it is a pretty basic human

16:27

capacity and it plays a very

16:29

important role in learning in particular.

16:32

And so I think there's one

16:34

version of that is very obvious because it's

16:36

so familiar to our everyday experience. But then

16:38

once you dig into it, it gets a little bit more

16:40

peculiar. So so one thing to

16:42

think about is that I very

16:44

straightforward why there would be some sort of adaptive

16:46

benefit for humans to be good predictors.

16:48

For example, right? If we could predict what's

16:50

gonna happen, that's clearly

16:52

very beneficial. We couldn't anticipate our

16:54

circumstances. We're going to know what's going to

16:56

happen if we intervene to find something about and so

16:58

on. But Explanation is different

17:00

from merely predicting. Explanations

17:02

are typically backwards looking, so we observe something

17:04

that's already happened, and then we wonder why did

17:06

that happen, and we to out what

17:08

happened in the past. So it's maybe not super

17:11

obvious why it is that we would have this

17:13

practice of trying to

17:15

explain things and wanting things with a particular

17:17

type of explanatory structure, if the thing

17:19

that's actually useful for us is just to be able to

17:21

predict. And so what I've argued is

17:23

that actually we can make sense

17:25

of why explanations have some of the capacities they

17:27

do, some of the characteristics they do

17:29

rather in this backwards

17:31

looking sense where the thought

17:33

is that Our explanatory practices

17:35

and looking for explanations actually helps us

17:37

construct the sorts of intuitive theories about the

17:39

world that are going to help us

17:41

predict. Down the line. Okay.

17:44

So to give you here's

17:46

here's one example of something

17:48

along these lines. So one of the phenomena that

17:50

I'm really interested is that we seem to learn better

17:52

by explaining to ourselves or to other

17:54

people. Right. Which is a little bit puzzling

17:56

because when you explain to yourself or to somebody else, you

17:58

don't get new information. Right? If you give me an explanation,

18:00

you've given me something new. But if I'm explaining to

18:02

myself, I'm just rearranging the pieces that are already in my

18:04

head. So

18:06

What's going on there? So we construct all of these lab studies

18:08

where we compare people who are learning

18:10

some tasks by explaining to themselves

18:12

versus doing something else. Like

18:14

thinking aloud or describing some sort of controller comparison

18:17

task. And we find that the people who

18:19

are explaining to themselves actually

18:22

learn better. They learn certain kinds

18:24

of regularities in the environment better than those who don't.

18:26

So for example, they're more likely to

18:28

identify subtle patterns

18:30

that differentiate two categories that they're

18:32

trying to learn to differentiate. So

18:34

Sorry. Can you can you elaborate on

18:36

what the two choices are? Like, one person

18:38

is is seeking an explanation and

18:40

the other person is doing what?

18:42

That's right. So it varies across across

18:44

experiments because there's no perfect control condition.

18:47

But to make us all more concrete, Suppose

18:49

you come into the lab, then you're in one of these experiments. Your

18:51

task is going to be to learn to categorize

18:53

new types of robots. Okay? And I'm

18:55

gonna show you Eight examples of

18:57

robots four belong to. Gorb the Gorb

19:00

category and four belong to the Drent

19:02

category. So you're gonna have four labeled examples of

19:04

each type of robot. And you're gonna study

19:06

these in order to figure out how

19:08

to differentiate corpse and dents because I'm gonna show

19:10

you some new robots later and you're gonna have to tell me

19:12

if they're corpse or dents. So I'm looking for

19:14

the pattern. Exactly. So

19:16

everybody in our task is basically

19:18

trying to find what what the pattern is in these

19:20

stimuli that will allow them to

19:22

generalize to new cases. So here's what

19:24

we manipulate. Half the participants,

19:26

as they're studying the globes and the dents, get

19:28

asked an explanation question. So we ask them,

19:30

like, why do you think this one's a glob? Why do

19:32

you think this one's a drent? And they try to come up with an

19:34

explanation, and we don't tell them if they're right or wrong,

19:36

so they're not getting any feedback, but they're engaged

19:38

in explanation seeking. And

19:40

we compare what they learn to

19:42

participants in a control condition. And the

19:44

control condition we we varied across studies,

19:46

it could be describe the scope,

19:48

describe the strength, So they're

19:50

being forced to use language. They're being forced to

19:52

pay attention to the task. We could

19:54

ask them to think aloud. Just tell us

19:56

what you're thinking as you are studying this

19:58

corporate rent. We could give them no

20:00

instructions at all, but give them an opportunity to

20:02

study so that everybody basically has the same task,

20:04

has the same data. Now we we design

20:06

the stimuli, these corpse and drens or whatever whatever we're

20:09

studying that particular experiment, so

20:11

that there's some relatively

20:13

subtle pattern that

20:15

you might discover that differentiates the Korps

20:18

syndrome. There's other things going on too,

20:20

but maybe it only accounts for half of the Korps

20:22

syndrome or seventy five percent of the

20:24

Korps syndrome. The only thing that it counts for,

20:26

you know, that all it only the trends

20:28

have versus all it only the groups of this sort of

20:30

subtle pattern. And what we find is that the

20:32

participants who are prompted to explain are

20:34

significantly more likely than those in

20:36

these alternative conditions to discover

20:38

that. So what's going on there? Well, it looks

20:40

like by virtue of the fact that they were trying

20:42

to explain they learned

20:44

something real about the

20:46

structure of these stimuli. And they learned it

20:48

faster and better. Sorry? They

20:50

learned it faster and better than they would

20:52

have otherwise. That's right. That's right. That's right. And so

20:54

it seems like there's something about

20:56

human explanation seeking that at

20:58

least for particular kinds of structure in

21:00

the world, might be especially

21:02

good at making us formulate

21:04

useful hypotheses, test them

21:06

in effective ways and come

21:09

up with sort of a good way of

21:11

characterizing some real generalization in the And this

21:13

is a place where you might think simplicity is beneficial

21:15

even if the world is not simple. By

21:17

virtue of trying to find a simple pattern, we might

21:19

sort of look harder and try harder and

21:22

discover whatever structure is actually there

21:24

even if the structure that's there is not

21:26

itself simple. And in the

21:28

clips and dents are the

21:30

patterns that they will ultimately find,

21:32

ones that they can

21:34

corporate kind of functionally for the robot their

21:36

little robots so they have a preexisting idea

21:38

of what robots might do? Or is it

21:40

just like this one has stripes and this one

21:43

has spot? We've done the

21:45

studies both ways. So

21:47

sometimes they're totally arbitrary features that don't seem

21:49

very meaningful. So for example, some of

21:51

them have feet that are pointy at the bottom and some of them

21:53

have feet that are flat at the bottom. And you can

21:55

come up with reasons why that might matter for

21:57

being a corporate veteran, but I don't know a lot

21:59

about Galp syndrome. So probably not In other versions,

22:01

we actually give people more information that would allow

22:04

them to make that be meaningful. So for

22:06

example, we tell them that some of these are indoor robots

22:08

and some of them are outdoor robots. And

22:10

now all of a sudden, you can kinda come up with some

22:12

reasons why foot shape might matter. Maybe

22:14

they'll they'll, you know, scratch the wooden floor if they

22:16

have pointy feet and but that makes

22:18

sense on type of

22:20

material. And what we find there is that

22:22

explaining makes you more likely to

22:24

discover the sort of simple

22:26

pattern that accounts for all cases either

22:28

way but that when you have this rich background information,

22:31

you use that more when you're

22:33

trying to explain. And I think that

22:35

makes sense when about

22:37

explanation everyday cases. A lot of what explaining looks like

22:39

is trying to make sense of new observations in

22:41

the context of what we already know. We're trying

22:43

to sort of like fit it in to what

22:45

our existing beliefs and intuitive theories of the world

22:48

are. And so when we prompt people to explain,

22:50

we see them doing that more. They're sort of trying to come

22:52

up with a story like,

22:54

why pointing versus flat feet would make

22:56

sense given that they're inboard versus out for

22:58

robots? Yeah. I mean, maybe this is a crazy

23:00

overgeneralization, so correct me if I'm

23:02

wrong, but It seems that over and over again, we see

23:04

examples where we have an

23:06

idea of what acting in a perfectly

23:08

rational way would be and

23:10

human beings come close to it but not really

23:12

because they're doing something completely different than

23:14

being rational for other completely other

23:16

reasons, but nevertheless, the reasons have

23:18

led them to sort of mimic rationality in some

23:21

kind of way. Howard Bauchner: Yeah, no, I don't think that's another

23:23

generalization at all, and I think that's

23:25

a really interesting way to think about this.

23:28

In this particular case, one

23:30

thing that I have come to think is

23:32

that there might be a story about why it's

23:34

rational to prefer simpler explanations

23:36

for example or explanations with other kinds of structures,

23:39

but it's not the one that we might have thought. So I

23:41

think the the intuitive idea

23:43

is the idea that I think Knewton

23:46

advocated. He has this lovely quote in the prepared, yeah,

23:48

which is something like, you know, when he said he

23:50

said we should basically prefer simpler

23:52

explanations because nature

23:54

affects not the pump of

23:57

superfluous causes. Right.

23:59

So so the thought is something like, if

24:01

nature itself is simple, then we

24:03

should prefer simple explanations because those

24:05

simple explanations are more likely to

24:07

accurately reflect nature. Right. And so that

24:09

would give you one reason why

24:11

preferring simple explanations would be rational.

24:14

And I'm skeptical of that one. I'm really

24:16

skeptical of that. But I

24:18

think what our data might suggest is

24:20

that having the practice

24:22

of preferring simpler explanations

24:24

might lead you to learn

24:26

about your environment and look for

24:29

particular types of structure in your

24:31

environment in a way that might have the positive

24:33

downstream consequence of leading you to

24:35

discover the structure that's actually

24:37

there. And so it's almost more like a methodological

24:41

strategy to get you to the

24:43

right place. But without the

24:45

assumption that the world is itself simple.

24:47

Right? It's rather that having

24:49

humans be sort of picky about explanations is

24:51

gonna be something that motivates go

24:53

out there and figure out what's really going on. Because the world

24:55

is a weird mixture of simple and complex.

24:58

Right? And we As a

25:00

psychologist, I'm gonna say more

25:02

complex than simple. But yeah. We

25:04

have to work hard to find the

25:06

simplicity, I guess, is is the plan I'm trying

25:08

to make. And and and we do, like like like

25:10

you just said. I guess I didn't

25:12

want to let go of the intriguing thing you

25:14

said about explanations being

25:17

mostly looking backward in

25:19

time rather than predictive in some

25:21

sense. I mean, it makes me think of mystery

25:23

novels. We love mystery novels. I love

25:25

mystery. And mostly

25:27

detective is trying to come up with an explanation for something that

25:29

happened in the past without necessarily

25:31

helping us predict the future on the

25:33

basis of that, but can

25:35

we conceptualize it as part of a

25:37

larger strategy that if we know why all

25:39

these murders are committed that will help us in the

25:42

future or is there something else going

25:44

on? I think there might be two things going on. So I think sometimes

25:46

we care about the backwards looking part

25:48

because we hold people causally

25:50

or morally responsible. Right? And there it

25:53

seems like that judgment is really

25:55

playing almost more of a social

25:57

role in how we regulate other people and

25:59

interact with other people. So that's

26:01

important. But I think also the practice of

26:04

explaining why particular events occurred

26:06

is going to be part of what allows us

26:08

to construct a causal model

26:10

that domain or just more generally sort of

26:12

a theory of that domain. And then it's

26:14

the theory of that domain that will allow us to

26:17

predict things in the future.

26:19

Right? So, you know, to give a

26:21

toy example, you might imagine that by

26:23

virtue of trying to figure out

26:25

a particular murder in this

26:27

detective story and so

26:29

on, somebody comes to learn something about human

26:31

motivations that they didn't appreciate before.

26:33

Mhmm. They come to learn something about

26:35

how particular poisons work and how you can mask their effects that

26:37

they didn't know before. Right? And so

26:39

they come to learn all of this particular stuff

26:42

that actually might be useful. In

26:44

the next case. You know, maybe not not narrowly for preventing another

26:47

murder, but but

26:49

it is contributing to your repository

26:51

of knowledge about the world. Yeah.

26:54

that is going to be useful in the future.

26:56

Yeah. I I guess I'm actually yeah. I'm

26:58

interested in this because I don't know

27:00

why the mystery

27:02

genre. I mean, in some sense, almost all

27:04

genres or subsets of mysteries. Right? Like,

27:06

things happen and we don't know why we wanna fix them

27:08

and It's a very it has a very powerful hold

27:10

on us psychologically and

27:13

I'm willing to buy that

27:15

it stems from the same impulse as

27:17

the impulse to, you know, understand and

27:19

predict the world going forward. May

27:21

maybe that is it or or maybe there's extra ingredients

27:24

being fed. Yeah. I think that's right. I I love

27:26

this example. The case I thought about a little bit more

27:28

is something like riddles. Mhmm. Right? We

27:30

find riddles extremely satisfying.

27:32

We're very curious about the answer to a

27:34

riddle. Very satisfied when we get the

27:36

answer to a riddle, but it's hard to

27:38

make the case that riddles play a fundamental role in

27:40

human learning. Right? It sort of seems like it's

27:42

the it's the candy of the system.

27:46

And I think the mystery novels might have

27:48

some of the same characteristics. Right? They

27:51

mimic some of these cases where we

27:53

really are prompted to find a next nation and where that's really central

27:55

to our ability to learn about the environment. Right.

27:57

And so they sort of like push all the right buttons

27:59

without necessarily giving us

28:01

the same adaptive

28:03

consequences that we may be seeing the explanation

28:05

case. Mhmm. But by

28:07

virtue of that structure, we we we do feel

28:09

drawn in. We are very curious. We do feel very

28:11

satisfied when there's a good resolution. Another

28:14

thing I don't let go of is

28:16

the relationship between explanations and

28:19

causes. You know, causality is

28:21

something that philosophers debate a lot

28:23

about. We had Judea Pearl on

28:25

the podcast. time ago. You know, it's

28:27

a whole subfield

28:29

of understanding causal influences on

28:31

things. Is it

28:33

okay to think about the search for explanation

28:36

as mostly a search for the cause

28:38

for why something happened? Or is there

28:40

a division between those sure

28:42

you know, there's a debate about this in philosophy,

28:44

and and I'd say probably in psychology

28:46

as well. My own view is that

28:48

a lot of explanation is causal, but

28:51

not all explanation is causal. I think one

28:53

of the clearest examples of non causal explanation

28:55

is mathematical explanation. Right? So you can give

28:57

an explanation for the Pythagorean theorem.

29:00

And it doesn't look like there's anything causal going

29:02

on there. And so, you

29:04

know, I think that raises a question about the

29:06

relationship between the causal cases and the non

29:09

causal cases. there really

29:11

fundamentally different kinds of explanations? I'm

29:13

more attracted to views that that think

29:15

that it's really very similar across these

29:17

kinds of cases that explanations in general

29:20

understanding that the nature of human

29:22

understanding involves something about

29:24

appreciating dependency relationships of a

29:26

particular Tania. might be multiple types of

29:28

dependency relationships, causal dependency

29:30

relationships are a really important type that

29:32

characterize huge swats of what we

29:34

care about, but not the only type. You

29:36

know, things can be can have a

29:38

deductive or an entailment relationship in the case

29:40

of mad, things can have a constitutive relationships.

29:42

So I think there's actually lots of other kinds of

29:44

relationships that can support explanations and explanatory

29:47

understanding. But by and large, the ones

29:49

that I've studied are the causal

29:51

cases. And I think those are the paradigm cases we

29:53

typically think about. It's interesting because, of course,

29:55

we don't agree on what

29:57

constitutes a causal case. You

29:59

know? And some people are gonna say,

30:01

well, pythagoras's theorem is

30:03

true because of

30:05

the postulates of Euclidean geometry.

30:08

And, you know, to me that's a

30:10

very different notion of the of

30:12

the word cause, then the

30:14

person died because they were stabbed by

30:16

their friend or whatever. I mean, we're using the same

30:18

word, but these are very different

30:20

philosophical concepts, I think. Howard Bauchner: I think that's

30:22

right. I mean, I think I think it's tricky to

30:24

interpret because Carroll's you

30:26

know, we use because in in all sorts of ways and at

30:28

least I would hesitate to to say that

30:30

they're all causal. You

30:33

know, we did some research in my lab that

30:36

tried to narrow in on a part of your question.

30:38

So we thought, what's the

30:40

most minimal contrast

30:42

between a cause claim and an

30:44

explanation claim. Okay. And so we had

30:46

cases where, for example, a causes

30:49

b, or be because a.

30:51

Right? And so the thought is they're, you know,

30:53

kind of as close as possible basically. But

30:55

but one's one's an explanation talk and one's

30:57

in causal talk. And we found that these

30:59

two behaved very, very similarly

31:02

in terms of what sorts of evidence

31:04

people thought was relevant for assessing whether or

31:06

not the claim was true, but we did find

31:08

some differences Right? Today's one identical. So here's

31:10

where maybe I'll give you a concrete case and get

31:12

an intuition or how these worked. So we

31:14

wanted cases where there were causal Carroll's. Where

31:17

people would not antecedent we think were related

31:19

at all. So one of our cover

31:21

stories involved, you

31:23

had to imagine that you've gone to work for a

31:25

museum, and one of your task is to tabulate

31:27

lots of data about the museum, you know, who

31:29

visits, which exhibits, and what they do, and

31:32

so on. And you just notice this

31:34

correlation in all of your data. There's a

31:36

correlation between having visited the portrait

31:38

gallery in the museum and

31:40

having made an optional donation when

31:42

you leave the museum. Good. Okay. So one thing we

31:44

can vary now is what's the strength of that correlation? Is

31:46

it just like a really weak association or

31:48

is it like pretty much a perfect

31:51

relationship. You know, every single all and only the

31:53

people who went to the portrait gallery, bit not foundation

31:55

and so on. And we ask people

31:57

claims like, To what extent do you agree that visiting the

31:59

portrait gallery caused this person to

32:01

make an optional donation as a left a

32:03

museum? Or why did this person make an optional

32:05

donation when a left a museum because they

32:07

is a project gallery. Right? So that we have the kind of matched cause of claims and

32:09

explanation claims. K? So the stronger the

32:11

statistical evidence that there is

32:13

a relationship, the more people are willing to

32:15

endorse these claims. But that

32:18

has a bigger effect for the causal

32:20

claim than for the explanation claim.

32:22

Here's here's here's the on the flip side what we found.

32:24

Yeah. Now we give some of

32:26

our participants a mechanism linking these two

32:28

things. Right? So if we constructed our

32:30

stimuli correctly for what we're going for, it should

32:32

hopefully not be at all obvious why there would

32:34

be a correlation here and

32:36

what might that? we tell half of our participants that actually there's a

32:38

lot of research in social psychology showing that

32:41

if you're surrounded by watchful others,

32:44

like in a portrait gallery with eyes and faces.

32:46

That triggers these mechanisms where

32:48

you're concerned with your reputation and leads

32:50

you to act more socially and so on.

32:52

And so you're more likely to do something like make an

32:55

optional donation. Okay. So when you give

32:57

people the mechanism that makes

32:59

them more likely to accept

33:01

the cause it more likely to accept the explanation claim that the reason

33:03

the person for example donated was

33:05

because they were in the portrait gallery. But

33:07

that has a bigger impact

33:09

on the explanation claim than not in

33:11

the causation claim. So, you know,

33:13

what is What is the probability of this? This is

33:15

tricky. Yeah. Okay. Good. So so that

33:17

that is a bigger impact on

33:19

the claim that they donated because

33:22

they went to the portrait gallery than it

33:24

does on the claim that the

33:26

going to the portrait gallery cause them

33:28

to donate. Exactly. Very fine

33:30

distinction. We're drawn here. But, okay, good. Yes.

33:32

That's right. But, I mean, part of the reason I maybe we wanted to be

33:34

a fine distinction really trying to drive a wedge

33:36

between these otherwise extremely similar

33:39

claims. Right? The kind of like bear calls will claim,

33:41

the bear explanation claim. So that's just

33:43

the empirical finding. But of course, I think the

33:45

more interesting question is, like, why? Right? What does this tell

33:47

us about the nature of explanation and causation and

33:50

so on? So what we think might be going on is that

33:52

this might give us some hints towards

33:54

what the functional role

33:56

of explaining is for people. Right? What do we want

33:58

our explanations to do for us? Such that we'd

34:01

be more satisfied when we have, say, the

34:03

mechanism information in this case. And

34:05

what we argue in this work is that one of the

34:07

reasons why mechanism information might be so

34:09

central to explanation is because mechanism information is what

34:11

allows us to generalize to new

34:13

cases. So suppose I now ask you to imagine

34:15

a case where some of the patrons of

34:17

the museum visit the

34:20

sculpture garden. And you need to predict whether or not those who visit garden

34:22

are also more or less likely to make

34:24

an optional donation. Well, if you

34:27

have the mechanism, you have a

34:30

basis for making that prediction. You might want to know,

34:32

well, where the sculptures

34:34

figured it? Did they involve faces?

34:36

If so, I'm going to predict that you're more make

34:38

a donation. If these were all

34:40

abstracts, sculptures, then no. You have no

34:42

reason to think that you're more likely to make a donation.

34:44

So by virtue of knowing the mechanism,

34:47

you are able to generalize from the original

34:49

case outside of the data that

34:51

you'd already observed. By contrast, if you

34:53

only have the correlation,

34:55

or the statistical evidence there. That tells you how

34:58

strong the relationship is in the

35:00

population that you studied already. But

35:02

it doesn't give

35:04

you guidance for how to generalize from that population to a novel

35:06

population. And so part of what we think

35:08

is so key about explanation is that it's

35:10

going to

35:12

direct you make you look for the sorts of things that support generalization.

35:14

And this ties back to our earlier discussion about

35:16

how explanation might support prediction.

35:18

Right? If what explaining is making you

35:20

do is

35:22

not just on any kind of structure in your environment, but

35:24

specifically the kind of structure that's likely to

35:26

be useful for generalizing to new

35:28

cases for predicting the future, then that would

35:30

make a lot

35:32

of sense. It does. So in other words, what what

35:34

looking for a good explanation is

35:36

about is more than just finding

35:38

a pattern but finding a

35:40

pattern that sort of fits into the rest of our

35:42

knowledge of the world in such a way that it has

35:44

some implications for other things we might

35:46

say going forward. That's right. That's right. And I think

35:48

that it helps explain by merely

35:50

predicting something accurately doesn't give

35:52

us a sense of understanding and explanatory sense of

35:54

satisfaction. If you had a black box

35:56

that allowed you to predict lots of

35:59

things very accurately. no idea how to

36:01

use it to get

36:03

to new cases. That's not

36:05

going to give you what we want in explanations even though

36:07

you're getting some predictive leverage there. Howard

36:10

Bauchner: It is weird because

36:12

in certain corners of

36:14

modern physics. I'm I'm bringing up physics

36:16

more than average in this philosophy

36:18

in this psychology But there's a

36:20

movement be precisely because some

36:23

modern theories of physics invoke

36:25

things we can't observe. Right?

36:27

Like the multiverse or string theory or whatever,

36:30

there's a sort of countervailing argument

36:32

that says, all I care about is

36:34

making predictions

36:36

for observations. And, you know, we have to stand up for the idea that no,

36:38

actually, I I wouldn't know why. I wouldn't actually

36:40

know the explanation. Some people are

36:42

are moving away from

36:44

that. So I'd like

36:46

it. I like the idea that

36:48

it's really the knowing why

36:50

that is the goal here, not merely

36:52

recognizing the existence of a pattern. That's right. Although I

36:54

think in the physics cases, you get to a real

36:56

question, which at least for me is an open question, which

36:58

is what are the limits of that? Right? Are there going to

37:00

be cases

37:02

where human mind is not capable of understanding the why. The best we can do

37:06

is is predict in some cases or rely

37:08

on our deep learning system or extremely

37:10

complicated theory do the predicting for

37:12

us. So I think that

37:14

is as an account of the psychology

37:16

of explanation -- Uh-huh. -- I think we really do

37:18

care about the why. And then thinking about what

37:20

does that mean for science? I think in that case,

37:22

you really come up against these cases where

37:24

it might turn out that some things are

37:26

beyond our our human capacities. It's possible, but I don't think we're there

37:28

yet, so I'm not worried about that. Like, if that comes

37:30

up to them, then I'll to be

37:32

optimistic about this. Thank you. I do.

37:34

I do. And

37:36

I guess this has been implicit in some of the things

37:38

we said, but from the psychological angle,

37:41

have we learned what

37:44

counts as a good explanation. I I think we all have ideas about what

37:46

counts as a good one. Again, making

37:48

ability to predict the future, fitting

37:51

into other things we think?

37:53

Or is it like an accepted set of criteria

37:55

for what an explanation is a good one?

37:57

Yeah. There's sort of there's sort of two questions, and I

37:59

think we have partial answers to both. One is what even counts

38:01

as an explanation. Right? So that

38:03

contrast is really with an explanation versus an odd explanation. And for that,

38:06

I think an explanation

38:08

typically generates

38:10

understanding about why

38:12

what you're asking about with the case as opposed to some often implicit

38:14

contrast. Right? So if I

38:17

say, you know, why why

38:20

is the sky blue? I might be implicitly asking

38:22

why is it blue as opposed to another color,

38:24

and an explanation has to generate understanding about

38:27

why it's blue as opposed to another color. You

38:29

might very legitimately then say what do you mean by

38:31

understanding there and we can come back to that. But I want to

38:33

contrast that with the question more the way you formulated it, which

38:35

is more like given that something is an explanation or

38:38

being offered as an explanation, what makes it a good

38:40

explanation or

38:42

satisfying explanation? And there we know a

38:44

bunch of features that seem to play Central. So

38:46

we've been talking about simplicity.

38:48

That seems to be one of them. And there seemed to

38:50

be a few different notions

38:52

of simplicity. So we can unpack that further and talk about kind of

38:54

simplicity. Brett seems to

38:56

be another one. So we like explanations

38:58

that explain everything we invoke

39:00

them to explain, not just sort of subsets

39:02

of it? You do.

39:04

Being consistent with your prior beliefs, as as

39:06

you've already suggested, to sort of fit in with what you

39:08

already know. People like

39:10

explanations better that don't make

39:12

unprecedented predictions.

39:14

Right? So something predict something that hasn't

39:18

been observed that might feel a little bit don't

39:20

that so much in our explanation. Isn't that the

39:22

opposite of what philosophy of science is

39:24

supposed to tell us

39:26

that we love the

39:28

explanations that had that make predictions that haven't

39:30

been tested yet because then we can go test

39:32

them? Yeah. That's not what the psychology suggest,

39:34

but, yes, I it it it the psychology result here is So is

39:36

this is a body of work focusing

39:38

on what they call latent scope.

39:40

And the idea

39:42

is that It's

39:44

thought of typically as an error. But for

39:46

example, if you have two diseases that could explain

39:48

a set of symptoms, one of them

39:51

predicts we blood test that we haven't yet done yet,

39:53

you'd see an abnormal value and the other

39:55

one predicts that you'd actually see a normal

39:58

value. People seem to prefer the theory

40:00

that does not make the

40:02

unverified prediction that may be departure

40:04

from the default. Mhmm. Even in conditions where you

40:06

statistically control for various things. So that seems like

40:08

it may be maybe an error, although it's perhaps an error

40:11

we can understand as an overgeneralization of a strategy

40:13

that makes sense under some

40:16

conditions. Sure. Other cases like this are sometimes I sometimes call them

40:18

explanatory vices as exposed to explanatory

40:20

virtues because it's not clear

40:22

that they're They're

40:24

always rational strategies for evaluating explanations. But to give you

40:26

other examples, people do prefer explanations sometimes

40:29

that involve reductive jargon. So

40:31

the classic case of this is that if you give people explanations

40:34

for psychological phenomena that

40:36

do or don't invoke totally irrelevant

40:38

neuroscience, at least that neuroscience is

40:40

irrelevant according to experts. Sure. You

40:42

typically find that late people like

40:44

those explanations better with that redact

40:46

of jargon.

40:49

There is a similar finding. It was in the context of scientific

40:51

abstracts rather than explanations, but people

40:54

were seduced by irrelevant math.

40:56

Right? So if you add some irrelevant math in there,

40:58

maybe that makes it seem. More

41:00

legit and might more rigorous. I'll do that

41:02

all the time. It's so good. Nice. It's

41:04

irrelevant. But the novice

41:07

maybe can't. People tend to

41:09

like explanations that offer a mechanism. We've

41:11

talked about that already.

41:14

You know, there's other characteristics like this. I think part of

41:16

what's challenging is that for any one of these,

41:18

there's a question of how you really define

41:22

that. Like, so for example, what do we mean was to say an explanation broader

41:24

and so on? And also, most of these

41:26

do show some context sensitivity.

41:29

And that makes very hard to make unqualified

41:32

generalizations. So to give you an example with respect to

41:34

simplicity that we've been talking

41:36

about, people also seem to

41:38

have this view that very complex

41:40

phenomena might require a more complex

41:42

explanation. And so

41:44

even though they generally seem to prefer simpler explanations for

41:46

a very complex phenomenon. You might actually

41:48

see something that goes a little bit the other

41:50

way where they start to think that,

41:52

you know, some

41:54

complexity is required in the explanation itself. Okay.

41:56

Good. Yeah, I can see that in in

41:59

different context. And I wonder But

42:02

there must be, like, I guess, different

42:04

people react to different ones of different of these

42:06

standards differently. Sorry. I'm

42:09

not articulating this very well, but I mean, maybe some

42:11

people are more in it for the simplicity, some people

42:13

are more in it for the scope, some people are more

42:15

in it for the fit to existing

42:18

knowledge, things like that. Yeah, I think that's

42:20

right. So I think that's an area where we actually just don't

42:22

have meant much data. So

42:24

far, there's a little bit. The data that is

42:26

there does address that there are there's

42:28

individual variation across people and the extent to which, for example, they want the mechanistic details.

42:30

And I think we all know this from everyday life.

42:32

There's a people who are just happy

42:35

to -- Oh, yeah. -- you showed them a microwave for the first time and

42:37

they're like, great. You know, I know it's button to push and that's

42:39

it. And there's the person who really wants to understand, like, well,

42:41

what's going on into the hood? So that's

42:43

a dimension of individual variation that's been documented. In explaining other

42:45

people's behavior, you also find

42:47

variation in the extent

42:49

to which people are open

42:51

to there being more complex interactions between a

42:54

person in their environment versus tending to

42:56

think that it's sort of like a more simple

42:58

straightforward explanation just in terms of

43:00

the person. I'm weirdly the person who does not know

43:02

the details sometimes. Like, when I'm

43:04

at the dentist and I was like, would you like to see

43:06

the what what we're doing to your teeth?

43:09

No. I no desire whatsoever to see that. Just

43:12

make it work. Just make them

43:14

healthy. I think you've

43:16

also written about some things

43:18

that maybe I don't know if they count as

43:20

explanations or not, but there's the idea of an explanation as

43:22

kind of an abstract framework, but

43:24

there's the strategy of telling

43:26

a story or an

43:28

anecdote or a narrative.

43:30

And sometimes people are gonna

43:32

count that or even prefer that in terms of

43:34

being an explanation. Yeah, I think those

43:36

cases are fascinating. Part of the reason I started to

43:38

think about it was because most of my

43:40

research is really focused on the role of explanation

43:42

and learning. Suggesting that explanation is important for generalization and so

43:44

on. And for for

43:46

that story to work, you really want

43:48

explanations to be focusing on relatively

43:50

abstract, generalizable

43:52

features of a situation. That's what we tend to look for in Right? We like science.

43:54

We like explanations in both laws and

43:57

things like that. And

44:00

so I was trying to reconcile that with this other everyday

44:02

human behavior, which is that you ask someone why

44:04

they relate to work. And they

44:07

don't give you some abstract generalization. They say, like, oh, my gosh, you

44:09

won't believe the morning I've had. Right? And then they'll tell you

44:12

about, you know, the play by

44:14

play leading up to their being way

44:16

to work. And that feels

44:18

much more like storytelling or narrative.

44:20

Mhmm. And so the way I think about this

44:22

now is I think there's sort of a continuum

44:24

between these. I think very often everyday

44:26

human explanations can sort of

44:28

be at an intermediate point, sort of giving

44:30

you the very abstract and allizable

44:32

features of a situation versus

44:34

focusing on these concrete particulars. And I think

44:36

they serve different functions. So I

44:38

think the the law

44:40

like generalizations are useful

44:42

precisely because they support generalization to

44:44

other cases. They're picking out the features of a

44:46

situation that are relatively invariant that

44:48

might support prediction to other cases and so

44:50

on. I think a lot of these

44:52

other things the concrete sensory

44:54

details. You know, the things that make

44:56

a piece of fiction really compelling, all of

44:58

that extra

45:00

nuance in detail. I think part of what that's doing

45:03

is giving you

45:05

input that allows you to

45:07

do something like

45:10

a until simulation of the situation, works for yourself and somebody's

45:12

shoes. And so you understand

45:14

the situation from a particular

45:17

sort of embodied perspective. And that can

45:19

give you a kind of insight about

45:21

the particulars of that

45:24

situation that you might not get from

45:26

this more abstract perspective, you know. So for example, by virtue of hearing

45:28

about the play by play of your morning

45:30

and how you spilled your coffee and

45:32

so on, I'm

45:34

gonna be in a better position to appreciate how

45:36

you really felt and how it was

45:38

frustrating and what that might have led you to

45:40

to think or to feel or to say and

45:42

so on. And

45:44

so it might be partially a peculiarity

45:46

of the way human cognition works, but

45:48

it's partially by getting those

45:50

concrete particulars we can engage in those kinds of mental

45:53

simulations effective. No, that's a fascinating point, very

45:55

interesting. Is it is it almost a

45:57

mirror neuron situation? Oh, gosh.

46:00

I I think I'm gonna not speculate about

46:02

Amerinirons because I will

46:04

get myself in trouble. I certainly

46:06

don't think that that's I don't think that's

46:08

likely to be a necessary part

46:10

of this story. You see, I'm adding

46:12

on unnecessary neuroscience to make it a more

46:14

compelling explanation. Yeah. People are gonna think

46:16

it's a better obligation. Actually, we should

46:18

kind of mirror neurons. But

46:20

no, I I do like the idea that

46:22

somehow forget about mirror Carroll's, but

46:25

the embodiment of the explanation. Like, there's

46:27

a set of rules abstractly. Okay.

46:29

That's one thing. If I can picture

46:31

myself in it, that's another

46:34

level of appreciation of this purported explanation.

46:36

Right? That's right. That's right. I mean, sometimes and and

46:38

I think you see this reflected in in

46:40

natural language. And

46:42

a discussion of philosophy as well in terms of different kinds of understanding. You know, one kind

46:44

of understanding we talk about is the sort of understanding

46:46

where you say, you know, I

46:49

understand quantum mechanics. Or I understand, you know,

46:51

how to how to drive the pythagorean theorem or something

46:53

like that, where it seems to be this relatively

46:56

like abstract

46:58

kind of understanding. But then there's this other thing we do where we say like, oh, I really

47:00

understand where you're coming from. I really understand her. I

47:03

really understand the character in this book.

47:05

Or I feel understood. And

47:08

All of those notions seem to be much more like this sort of

47:11

first personal story narrative

47:13

like case. Mhmm. Where

47:16

we really can sort of put ourselves in the position of somebody else.

47:18

And so just just like I

47:20

think, you know, explanation and storytelling sort

47:23

this gamut. I think these different notions of understanding show

47:25

a similar kind of variation. I like that.

47:27

Is it also possible that the

47:29

storytelling end of the spectrum sort

47:31

of gets a bad rap? Because we

47:34

valorize rationality. That's what

47:36

they're saying. So I think I think it would

47:38

legitimately get a bad rap

47:40

if we used the concrete

47:42

storytelling to serve the

47:44

roles that should be served

47:46

by the more general explanation. Right?

47:48

So an example like that

47:50

might be somebody taking an anecdote to

47:52

be a good basis for a

47:54

public policy decision, for example,

47:56

rather than

47:58

looking at data and the generalizations that are actually available to us at this

48:00

large scale. And there is some evidence like

48:02

that. I mean, in the context of persuasion,

48:04

anecdotes and good stories are persuasive.

48:06

Oh, yeah. And

48:08

so those might be cases

48:10

where they legitimately get a bad rap

48:12

insofar as they are being mistaken

48:14

for strong evidence.

48:16

But on the other hand, I think they're

48:18

playing a really important role. Right? So I

48:20

think I think maybe what we need to

48:22

do is legitimize valuable roles for stories and

48:24

for that that mode of explanation as

48:26

long as we don't mistake it for playing

48:28

the role of giving us the abstract analysis.

48:31

And may maybe for empathy more

48:34

broadly, I did talk to Paul Blum on the

48:36

podcast and he made the opposite claim. He he

48:38

worried that people were too quick to be empathetic

48:40

and that sort of biased them

48:42

toward people like themselves, and they should try

48:44

to be more rational. And I tried to

48:46

say, well, but yes, we should the

48:48

solution to that is

48:50

not to not be empathetic, but to be empathetic to a broader

48:52

spectrum of people. And I'm not sure who's right

48:54

there. Yeah. I I'm

48:56

inclined to to say that there's

48:58

value to empathy, there's value to empathy

49:00

in a broader range of cases, but maybe we

49:02

shouldn't only rely on empathy. Right? That's just one

49:04

of the tools that we have for making sense of a

49:06

situation. So why does it have to

49:08

be rationality or empathy or you know what the utilitarian calculus or the

49:10

kind of empathic response? Maybe we should

49:12

see what each has to offer

49:15

and then integrate both of those into our overall

49:17

evaluation. Fair enough. So how often in this

49:19

whole game do you run across

49:21

the issue of what is the explanation for the explanation? Like,

49:23

is there a bottoming out of these explanations

49:26

anywhere? Are people at what point

49:28

are people satisfied to

49:30

say, like, okay, that's the explanation

49:32

I don't need to dig more deeply. I

49:34

wish I knew the answer to that question. We have

49:36

definitely thought about it. I can I can

49:38

tell you the crumbs we've picked out, you know, in the vicinity, but we

49:40

don't have an answer to

49:42

that. So one thing

49:44

that's really

49:46

interesting is that when you get a

49:48

satisfying explanation, that doesn't stop inquiry. Right? I mean, you might have

49:50

thought that you keep looking till you get a

49:52

satisfying explanation. And then once you get a satisfying explanation,

49:56

Like -- Yeah. -- you're least for kind

49:58

of rich real world cases, like

50:02

explanations for why the dinosaurs became extinct and

50:04

things like

50:06

that, you find is that when somebody received a satisfying explanation,

50:08

they're now more curious about follow-up questions. So

50:10

it's almost like they've found like, oh, there's there's

50:12

stuff to learn here. Good. This is valuable. is

50:16

rich and they keep going. Another thing that

50:18

we have a little bit of evidence for, this

50:20

is more tenuous, but I think it's plausible.

50:23

One place where questioning might stop is where you can't

50:25

imagine a plausible other way than things could

50:28

be. Right? So in order to ask a question like, why

50:30

is the sky blue? It seems like on

50:32

some level, you have to represent the

50:34

possibility that could have been

50:36

nonblue. Right? Yes. And

50:38

so it could be that some

50:40

of when where things bottom out is where you

50:42

just either don't or can't

50:44

represent a real alternative to the way that

50:46

things are. So if you

50:48

can't imagine something, nothing

50:50

existing instead of something, for example, then you might

50:52

not be puzzled by the question of why is there

50:54

something rather than nothing? It's only once you recognize

50:56

this alternative possibility that you're

50:58

able to ask the question, well, y x and not

51:00

y. Right? The y has to be there even

51:03

if it's implicit. scooped me. I was exactly

51:05

next gonna ask you an

51:07

entirely unfair question, which is what is

51:09

your feeling about the

51:12

question Why is there something rather than nothing? I mean, my feeling is that

51:14

that's the kind of grammatical construction

51:16

that looks like it's perfectly well formed,

51:20

but it doesn't actually apply. The world is not the kind of thing that

51:22

necessarily has an explanation

51:24

for why it exists. Yeah. That's interesting.

51:28

I don't know how to think about that case except to say that I I have a hard

51:30

time knowing what the alternative would be.

51:32

Right? And I think that's that's part of my having my

51:34

hard time wrapping around the -- Mhmm. -- I had

51:37

around the question. But as I said, our evidence for that is

51:39

indirect. I don't think I have any great evidence to speak

51:42

to the something rather than nothing question. I mean, I

51:44

will say something, but I think it's

51:46

also sort related to this, which is that

51:48

we found variation in the cases where people are willing to accept that something

51:50

is a mystery. Okay. And so

51:54

we'll try out your intuitions here. So if I said something like,

51:56

why does the moon cause the tides? It's

51:58

a mystery. I mean, that just seems

52:01

or not just because you probably not just because

52:03

you probably actually know something about the

52:05

the physics there, but, like, that's

52:07

the sort of thing. That's not like, it can't be

52:09

a mystery. Right. But if I say something like,

52:11

why does God answer prayer? And I say this

52:14

to somebody who is a believer and

52:16

believe that theories of God

52:18

and God answers prayer and so on. It's a

52:20

mystery. That seems much more

52:22

acceptable. Right. And so that's that's something we

52:24

find as a reliable domain difference. Where people tend think

52:26

that scientific questions sort of

52:28

demand an explanation more than religion questions

52:31

that it's more acceptable to say

52:33

that it's a mystery. For

52:35

the religion questions and for the science

52:37

questions. And we find variation for other things

52:39

in between. I'm not entirely sure what to

52:42

make of this, but philosophy and psychology

52:44

fall somewhere. Between -- Okay. -- National Science had

52:46

had religion in terms of people's willingness

52:48

to sort of accept its mystery

52:50

claims. And so I think part of this has to

52:52

do with

52:54

the perceived limits of human comprehension. That seems to be part of the

52:56

story. We have some data for that, but that isn't the whole

52:58

story. There also seems to be variation across these

53:00

cases and what people think we should

53:04

try to explain. So some people have the sense that some things are appropriate

53:06

targets for explanation and inquiry. Other

53:08

things are not appropriate targets for explanation and inquiry,

53:10

and that's going to be another factor that affects

53:13

I think where explanations bottom out. If you hit a

53:15

point where people no longer think either either think

53:17

it's a mystery or no longer think it's an

53:19

appropriate target for inquiry, you're presumably going to

53:21

stop asking why. But I wonder if

53:23

much is attributable to the kinds of science questions

53:26

that that we're interested in

53:28

here? Because Yeah.

53:30

Why God doesn't answer prayers? Alright.

53:32

That's a mystery. Why

53:34

the moon causes the tides? Is

53:37

not, but then you say, oh, well, because it's gravity this way. But, okay, why does

53:39

gravity work in this way? Well, it has something to

53:41

do with the curvature of spacetime.

53:43

Okay. Why is space time group.

53:45

Like at some point, you will bottom out

53:48

and I think that what the scientists

53:50

would say is that's just how

53:52

it is. There is no further

53:54

explanation, but is that very

53:56

different than saying it's a

53:58

mystery? So we do find this

54:00

subtle difference. In our data where it's a mystery is not

54:02

exactly the same as it's unknown.

54:04

Okay. So in the case of these science

54:06

questions, the

54:08

modal form of ignorance that people expresses, it's unknown to me,

54:10

whereas for religion, the modal

54:12

form of ignorance that people expresses, it's

54:16

a mystery. Not just to me, just

54:18

it's a mystery full style. Interesting. I

54:20

don't know how to think about those fundamental physics

54:22

cases, but people think it's sort of merely unknown,

54:24

merely unknown to them. It noble to everybody? Is it

54:27

deep down the mystery? You know, empirically,

54:29

I have no data there. My

54:31

my own personal sense

54:33

is that it's unknown, but in such

54:35

an unsatisfying way. Right? We

54:38

really really want more and

54:40

think we probably aren't gonna get it. And that might

54:42

be part of what when we call something a

54:44

mystery part of what we might be saying is it's

54:46

unknowable. You know, we've kind of hit a hard, it's

54:48

hard limit. It's not just something that's merely

54:50

unknown now. But this idea of

54:52

what is satisfying to us is so

54:54

crucial. And I do find myself

54:56

sometimes when people demanding to know

54:58

something big

55:00

picture philosophical scientific question,

55:02

I'll I'll give what I think is the best explanation and

55:04

then you say, like, I'm just not satisfied with that. And

55:06

I had to

55:08

say, well, No one ever promised you, you would be satisfied

55:10

with the correct scientific explanation.

55:12

So I think that that desire to be

55:14

satisfied is on the one hand crucially important.

55:16

On the

55:18

other hand, hard to really justify on any foundational That's

55:20

right. And I think that's part of what actually

55:22

that that sense of wanting something satisfying,

55:24

I think is part of what explains

55:28

why explanation plays a effective role in learning for humans. Right? That's

55:30

part of what it's like the motivational

55:32

wing of the exploratory explanation

55:36

seeking enterprise that we

55:38

engage in. So I think it plays an important role,

55:40

but I think there's going to clearly be cases

55:42

where it just sort of leaves

55:44

this way. You know, we're unsatisfied, but there's nothing more to more to say. And

55:46

I think I think a lot of coincidences have that

55:49

kind of character. Right? They sort of strike

55:51

us as things that are you

55:54

know, it it just seems like there there must be

55:56

something too -- Oh. -- the fact that, you know,

55:58

your birthday is the same as my

56:00

birthday and you know, can we can we can we can we do whatever? You know, make make up arbitrary

56:02

coincidences here. And at the end of the day, the

56:04

story is just like, well, I mean, of course, there's a callable

56:06

story about,

56:08

like, that's your birthday. There's some story about why this is my birthday, but there's

56:10

no further backed about us

56:12

both having the same birthday. That feels like,

56:15

that might feel really unsatisfied. So

56:18

I mean, I sometimes think that certain kinds of conspiracy

56:20

beliefs or other kinds of

56:25

crazy ideas that people talk themselves

56:27

into are motivated by these cases where

56:29

it really feels like there should be more to

56:31

say about why things happened the way they

56:33

did. It's really unsatisfying to just in a lot of

56:35

cases, hey, it was just chance. There's nothing

56:38

more to say about what seems like, you

56:40

know, simply calling out for explanation.

56:42

Well, I I agree. I think

56:44

that it's again, it's very hard

56:46

to articulate the degrees

56:48

with which we should accept

56:50

claims like it's just a

56:52

coincidence or it's just a mystery. Right? Like,

56:54

we do fight against that, but sometimes it's just

56:56

right. And I I don't know how exactly to

56:58

say when

57:00

that's okay. Yeah. That's right. I mean, I think I think part of it might be that we don't always know in

57:02

advance. Right? A lot of it might just it's gonna

57:04

be an empirical question. Right. We got

57:06

it right around in a given

57:08

case. And there's the error of thinking, there's nothing further

57:10

to learn.

57:12

When in fact, there is, and that seems like it's

57:14

a problematic error, and then there's the error

57:16

of continuing

57:18

to look. Uh-huh. And in fact, there was

57:20

no explanation. And that's also

57:22

problematic insofar as your spending

57:25

of resources and so on. But you might think that we're better

57:27

off being the kinds of creatures

57:29

who keep trying a little bit more than we should

57:31

because we're under some circumstances. And

57:33

the kinds of creatures who give up too soon? Well,

57:35

you mentioned that the religious in the

57:38

religious context, people are more

57:40

willing to put up with

57:42

mystery as a state of

57:44

explanatory progress. But

57:46

as I recall correctly, there's also some

57:48

different research you did on

57:52

religious versus non religious explanations, and and their

57:54

their connection to sort of

57:56

epistemic functions versus nonepistemic

57:58

functions. Like, the religious religious

58:00

explanations are doing something for us

58:02

other than just giving us knowledge

58:04

about the system. That's right. So what we did in

58:06

that research is that

58:08

we chose to look at explanations for existential

58:10

questions, things like where did the

58:12

universe come from and so on? Mhmm.

58:14

And part of what happens after

58:16

we die Part of reason we did

58:18

that is because those are questions where you

58:20

see people very often spontaneously

58:22

peeling to both religious and non religious sorts

58:24

of explanations. And so we had people

58:26

generate all sorts of explanations, and then we had other participants code

58:28

the characteristics of all of those explanations.

58:32

And some of those characteristics were what we would call broadly epistemic,

58:34

things like how much there's evidence for

58:36

that explanation to what extent it's based on evidence,

58:38

whether it's based on on logical documentation,

58:42

and so on. And we also had them evaluated for what we consider to be

58:44

non episodic characteristics. Like, does this

58:46

give you comfort? Does this reduce negative

58:48

emotions? Is this a sort of explanation

58:52

that promotes moral behavior that brings people

58:54

closer together and so on. So sort of a

58:56

host of social, moral,

58:58

and emotional kinds of

59:00

benefits. And so there were a few interesting results.

59:02

So one is just if you just, on average,

59:04

see what characteristics do people think these

59:06

explanations have, The scientific

59:08

explanations did better than the religious explanations on

59:10

these epistemic dimensions, like

59:12

evidence and logic, and

59:14

the religious explanations did better than the scientific

59:16

explanations. In terms of these nonepidemic

59:18

kinds of characteristics. But part

59:20

of what I think is interesting is that

59:23

you can further break that down by the

59:25

extent to which a given individual believes the explanation. Right?

59:27

So, you know, on a sort

59:29

of five point scale, strong they

59:31

do believe this explanation.

59:34

And we replicate these results for every

59:36

level of belief. So what that means is suppose

59:39

you have somebody two people who

59:41

both give a a given

59:44

religious explanation of four on this five point

59:46

scale. Even though they're giving it

59:48

the same they endorse

59:50

it equally strongly. They're still

59:52

going to say that the scientific one is better

59:54

than the religious one in terms of these

59:56

episodic dimensions and the religious is better than

59:58

in terms of non epidemic kinds of characteristics. I would like to

1:00:01

explain that. Oh, here's here's

1:00:03

here's here's one way to

1:00:06

here's here's a different way to describe it that I think is much more intuitive, and I don't have

1:00:08

the the figures here to point this out as

1:00:10

I as as I talk you through this, either with

1:00:12

you or with your listeners, you'll

1:00:16

have to Hopefully, this will make sense. One way

1:00:18

to make sense of that pattern of findings that I just

1:00:20

described is that people have

1:00:22

different thresholds

1:00:24

for scientific and religious explanations in order to be willing

1:00:26

to believe them at a certain level of confidence.

1:00:28

Okay. For a scientific explanation,

1:00:30

they demand a lot of evidence

1:00:33

and are less demanding with respect to the

1:00:35

nonepisemic characteristics. And before the religious

1:00:38

explanations, it's the reverse. They're very demanding

1:00:40

with respect the nonepisemic

1:00:42

characteristics, they have to meet a high threshold there for

1:00:44

them to believe it, but they're less

1:00:46

demanding with respect to the episodic

1:00:48

characteristics. Got it. Actually, that made perfect

1:00:50

sense. I think you did a very good job of explaining

1:00:52

that. And is this

1:00:54

something Tania particular to religion?

1:00:56

Or what is the pull of

1:00:58

nonepastemic factors when it comes to

1:01:00

us seeking explanations. Like,

1:01:02

I guess, to make it more concrete,

1:01:05

how often do people accept

1:01:07

an explanation for something because it

1:01:09

would lead to good behavior if

1:01:11

people felt that? Yeah, that's a great question. I mean, so one

1:01:13

important qualification that I should make about all of

1:01:16

the research I've talked about, about

1:01:18

religious explanations,

1:01:20

is that these are predominantly

1:01:22

Christian participants in the United States. Fair enough.

1:01:24

Good point. Yes. So when I say religion, I

1:01:26

really mean

1:01:28

that is the population we've studied and it might be different in other

1:01:30

cultures and for other culture traditions or other

1:01:32

religious traditions within the United States. I

1:01:34

think it's an important qualification. But

1:01:37

I think this is actually probably pretty

1:01:40

widespread. So if you think

1:01:42

about, you know, you suppose you have

1:01:44

to explain

1:01:46

why you why you forgot somebody's birthday or something

1:01:48

like that. What what's

1:01:50

gonna make that a good explanation? Well, you have

1:01:52

a lot of goals in giving that explanation.

1:01:56

And some of those goals are presumably more epidemic. I mean, you want to

1:01:58

say things that are true, you want to perhaps

1:02:00

instill true beliefs in the other person.

1:02:03

But you have a lot of other goals. I do.

1:02:05

Yes. You wanna you wanna not think

1:02:07

of yourself as a terrible person. You don't

1:02:09

want the other person to think about you

1:02:11

as a terrible person. And so I think it's

1:02:13

actually just very, very common in everyday explanations that

1:02:15

we're constantly juggling these kinds of epidemic and sorts

1:02:17

of goals, but also these non epidemic Carroll's.

1:02:19

We're constantly regulating

1:02:22

own emotion and other people's emotions. We're constantly thinking about the social

1:02:24

consequences, the moral consequences of what we

1:02:26

believe and other people believe. I I don't think this

1:02:28

always happens consciously and explicitly.

1:02:31

Sometimes we might self deceive ourselves

1:02:33

into the most charitable interpretation of why

1:02:35

we forgot somebody's birthday.

1:02:38

But that makes me think it's actually quite

1:02:40

widespread. Although, you know, it's hard to put a

1:02:42

number on this. And I don't have a number, so I don't

1:02:44

want to I don't want to claim. I have to

1:02:46

support the claim I just said, but that's that's what

1:02:48

my bet would be if we if we've found a good

1:02:50

way to measure that. Is it just hard being a psychologist

1:02:52

sometimes? Because you're too aware of why

1:02:55

you're doing different things for not

1:02:57

always the right reasons? Yes,

1:03:00

but also that's part of what's fun. Right? So for me, everyday

1:03:04

life provides all sorts of fodder for thinking about

1:03:06

the things that I like to think about.

1:03:08

Right. Does it how much

1:03:10

feedback is there? Does being a psychologist affect your

1:03:12

behavior? You know, I'll tell you about the most painful case

1:03:14

of that, which is that I I know I know I

1:03:16

know something about child development. My PhD was

1:03:18

or so cognitive development. I really wish I could tell you that made

1:03:20

me a better parent. I really, really wish

1:03:22

I could tell you that it did.

1:03:27

But mostly, I'm inclined to say no. I think it

1:03:30

probably makes me more

1:03:32

aware of shortcomings. I'm not

1:03:34

sure how much better it makes

1:03:36

me correcting those shortcomings.

1:03:38

Fair enough. I could absolutely believe that.

1:03:40

I mean, certainly being a physicist does not make me

1:03:42

a better billier's player or anything anything

1:03:45

like that. So it's perfectly fair. The

1:03:47

the practicalities of the real world do get in

1:03:49

the way. But but good because that leads me

1:03:52

to the last thing I wanted to ask about,

1:03:54

which was childhood development.

1:03:57

I mean, you mentioned it

1:03:59

a little bit, but it seems like

1:04:01

we are born with

1:04:04

this desire to explain. Can can

1:04:06

we pinpoint that at,

1:04:08

like, two years old, three years old, four years

1:04:10

old, whatever? Is it is there's a moment when

1:04:12

our explaining or

1:04:14

explanation seeking impulses kick

1:04:16

in? Yeah. So so as I mentioned, we do know

1:04:18

that basically as soon as kids have

1:04:20

the language to start asking

1:04:22

questions they do. And so you might think that

1:04:24

that's the earliest we can go. But there's a

1:04:26

couple of very clever

1:04:28

approaches, developmental psychologists have taken to

1:04:30

try to take this question earlier. I'll

1:04:32

you two of my favorite So

1:04:34

one was a study that tried to compare

1:04:36

explanation seeking in humans

1:04:38

and in nonhuman primates. And I'm

1:04:40

pretty sure this was a chimpanzees. And so that raises this really interesting puzzle,

1:04:42

which is what does explanation seeking look

1:04:44

like and how do you measure

1:04:47

it in a nonverbal organism.

1:04:50

And so what they did, which I think is very clever,

1:04:52

is they basically is an exploration

1:04:54

task. So they trained the participants

1:04:56

in this experiment to learn how to balance a

1:04:58

particular block in a particular Tania, and then

1:05:01

they gave them blocks that had internal

1:05:03

weights that would make them

1:05:05

not balance. So that you would try to balance them in the way that

1:05:07

you might think it would balance, it falls over, what

1:05:09

do you do? The thought is that if

1:05:11

you spontaneously are seeking

1:05:14

explanations, what you're gonna do is basically examine it, explore it,

1:05:16

try to figure out what's going on. And

1:05:18

so what they found was at, like, quite young

1:05:22

toddlers. Engaged in this kind of behavior. And so that's a really

1:05:24

nice nonverbal measure of sort of

1:05:26

spontaneous exploration that seems to be

1:05:28

explanation directed. Another thing

1:05:30

that people have done is look at looking

1:05:32

time with infants. Like, what do

1:05:34

infants look at? I'm sorry. Do you

1:05:36

do you do that? Also?

1:05:38

Sorry. Well, it's a little bit complicated. So

1:05:40

-- Okay. -- so mostly they did not.

1:05:42

But there's a really

1:05:45

important difference between experience for the toddlers

1:05:47

and for the primates in that study, which toddlers basically understood the task

1:05:50

immediately with very little

1:05:52

training, whereas the primates had to

1:05:54

have, like, can't

1:05:56

remember what it was, but dozens and dozens and dozens of trials to understand

1:05:58

that what they were supposed to be doing -- Got it. --

1:06:00

was taking these blocks and putting them somewhere. And so it's a

1:06:02

thin fabric. I'm not sure what to make of the fact

1:06:05

after that training regime. They didn't spontaneously explore

1:06:07

because it's not clear to me that they understood

1:06:09

what the task was and what was, you know.

1:06:12

Okay. So I that part of the

1:06:14

result I'm less confident than, but I think the methods

1:06:16

are just super clever. Howard Bauchner:

1:06:18

Thanks. The way

1:06:20

people have sort of thought about for infants is by looking

1:06:22

at what infants look at. Right? Because that's a behavior

1:06:24

that we can measure. And what you can

1:06:26

do is give them two little

1:06:30

sort of scenarios where

1:06:32

one involves something that's physically possible. So

1:06:34

for example, you try to balance a cup

1:06:36

on the edge of a table, and it's such

1:06:38

at the center of mass is on the table. Just, you know,

1:06:40

a little bit of the cup is off the table, and so

1:06:43

you might expect that that will not

1:06:45

fall versus one

1:06:47

where It's, you know, just barely touching the table, so an

1:06:49

adult would expect it to fall. And you

1:06:51

can do various kind of variations like this. But which

1:06:53

one is the kid the child can have the infant can look

1:06:56

more at? And for a lot

1:06:58

of cases like this, the infant spent more time looking at the

1:07:00

thing that is something

1:07:03

like a violation of a principle

1:07:05

or expectation. So the fact that they discriminate

1:07:08

those two pieces and how long they look

1:07:10

tells us something about what their expectations are,

1:07:12

about the way the world works. Now does it tell

1:07:14

us what they're explaining? This is now

1:07:16

much more controversial. But at least

1:07:18

some of the people who do this research have suggested

1:07:20

that part of what's going on when infants

1:07:23

observe these cases is that they try

1:07:25

to construct an explanation for what

1:07:27

they observed. So you're seeing a sort

1:07:29

of mechanism of explanation based learning in these

1:07:31

kinds of cases. And that part of the

1:07:33

way they form the relevant generalizations about their expectations in these cases is

1:07:35

by explaining the cases that they do observe. And

1:07:38

so it's possible that even that

1:07:40

looking behavior

1:07:42

reflects something like the infant looking for an explanation

1:07:44

for this otherwise anomalous event.

1:07:46

Have you seen these videos

1:07:48

where someone hides behind a blanket

1:07:51

and the dog is looking at them and then

1:07:53

they pretend to disappear when they let the

1:07:55

blanket go and the dogs kind of freaks out because the

1:07:57

person isn't there anymore. I haven't seen

1:07:59

the videos, but I can imagine them. I'm not a

1:08:02

phenomenon. Some other comment is one that's a date and

1:08:04

events. Well, that's -- Yeah. -- and and that's why I'm

1:08:06

asking because, you know, object

1:08:08

is that set count as an explanation or is that even more

1:08:10

primitive somehow? Like, if I decide the

1:08:12

distinction between that and the kid and the center

1:08:14

of gravity, yeah, I think that's right. I meant the truth is think

1:08:16

we don't yet know in the infant case

1:08:18

or in the doc case. I'll add that

1:08:20

into If

1:08:22

they're looking longer, if they're startled, I think

1:08:25

that shows something like an expectation.

1:08:27

Does it show something like

1:08:30

explanation seeking? I mean, if if if the dog then

1:08:32

went and, like, sniffed around where the person

1:08:34

was and sort of looked around, I

1:08:36

think that starts to get a little bit

1:08:38

more compelling. But what counts as a genuine nonverbal measure

1:08:41

of explanation seeking? It's just

1:08:43

a really challenging mathematical question.

1:08:47

Fair enough. Okay. I guess the final

1:08:49

thing then is does this maybe you

1:08:51

already answered it informally, but

1:08:53

do these insights

1:08:56

help us in thinking about how to

1:08:58

educate children or even educate ourselves as growing up adults, you know, like better

1:09:00

strategies for seeking explanations and

1:09:02

deploying them in the real world.

1:09:05

I think there might be two lessons, so one of them that I

1:09:07

should acknowledge has been well recognized in the education community as well, is that there are

1:09:09

benefits to explain to yourself and

1:09:12

to others. That's

1:09:14

one of the reasons why peer tutoring, for example, is so

1:09:17

effective. In fact, sometimes in peer tutoring

1:09:19

context, people who benefit more are the

1:09:21

tutors rather than the tutors. They have

1:09:23

the ones who doing the doing the

1:09:25

explaining. So I think that's one thing is just engaging an explanation seems to

1:09:27

be valuable. That's an activity

1:09:29

we could we could do

1:09:32

more of one version of

1:09:34

this that I think is very familiar is you think you understand something until you try to explain it to somebody

1:09:36

else. And then in the

1:09:38

course of doing so, you'd be

1:09:41

who don't. Right? So -- Right. -- if we

1:09:43

had if we engaged in that more spontaneously, we would catch those gaps

1:09:45

in our own understanding. We'd be better calibrated in what we do and

1:09:48

don't understand. So,

1:09:51

explaining is good in educational context. Good. Formal and

1:09:53

informal. The other one though is

1:09:55

that I think maybe we

1:09:57

should be a little bit

1:09:59

wary of expecting satisfying explanations when we look. Alright? I

1:10:01

mean, some of the times the world just really is

1:10:04

complicated. Yeah. Number

1:10:07

of the times, the explanation is not beautiful. So so while

1:10:09

I think explanation seeking is something

1:10:11

we should do, I think at the

1:10:13

same time, we have to at least be cognizant of the

1:10:15

fact that the explanations are not always going to be

1:10:18

beautiful or satisfying, willing to entertain the

1:10:20

possibility that the beautiful

1:10:22

or satisfying explanation is wrong.

1:10:24

I think that sounds very true and

1:10:27

very important, but it calls out for a well formulated theory of

1:10:30

when to stop looking. For

1:10:32

the explanation. And I think we previously agreed that's

1:10:34

pretty tricky question. I wish I had that. Alright. Maybe this is

1:10:37

this is can can figure that out for us.

1:10:39

No. I very much doubt that. I

1:10:42

think this is your job. You and the philosophers, but I

1:10:44

I've learned a lot. You've explained a

1:10:46

lot, and it again, it must be

1:10:49

weird not just being a psychologist, but you're constantly

1:10:51

trying to explain these facts about explanations, and it all gets a little

1:10:53

meta. So I think that we handled it. It

1:10:55

does pretty well. Tania Lombrozo, thanks

1:10:57

very much for being on

1:10:59

Mindscape Thanks for

1:11:02

having me. This

1:11:05

is bed bug.

Unlock more with Podchaser Pro

  • Audience Insights
  • Contact Information
  • Demographics
  • Charts
  • Sponsor History
  • and More!
Pro Features