247. Can Interest Rates Fall to Zero on the Free Market

247. Can Interest Rates Fall to Zero on the Free Market

Released Tuesday, 12th November 2024
Good episode? Give it some love!
247. Can Interest Rates Fall to Zero on the Free Market

247. Can Interest Rates Fall to Zero on the Free Market

247. Can Interest Rates Fall to Zero on the Free Market

247. Can Interest Rates Fall to Zero on the Free Market

Tuesday, 12th November 2024
Good episode? Give it some love!
Rate Episode

Episode Transcript

Transcripts are displayed as originally observed. Some content, including advertisements may have changed.

Use Ctrl + F to search

0:00

The Principles

0:02

of Economics

0:06

Principles of Economics, my complete guide

0:08

to understanding economics, is now available

0:10

in hardcover, audiobook and e-book from

0:12

safedean.com, Amazon and

0:14

many more booksellers worldwide. And

0:17

now I am also teaching a course

0:19

based on this book on my website

0:21

safedean.com. Principles of Economics

0:23

will run the whole academic year, from

0:26

September to June, and will have a

0:28

new lecture every two weeks, as well

0:30

as weekly live online discussion seminars open

0:32

to learners from all over the world

0:35

and from all walks of life. Whether

0:37

you are a student, a professional

0:40

or a retiree, you are making

0:42

economic decisions every day, and

0:44

this course will arm you with the

0:46

wisdom of centuries of economists to improve

0:48

your economic decision making. You'll

0:51

also get a free book of Principles of Economics if you sign

0:53

up for the course. Go to safedean.com

0:55

and sign up now. Good

1:04

morning and thank you everybody for coming, and thanks

1:06

again to Professor Hoppe and the Property and Freedom

1:08

Society for inviting me to speak today. I'm

1:11

going to discuss the topic of interest rates

1:13

on a free market. Now,

1:15

historically, interest is perhaps

1:18

one of the most controversial economic

1:20

and moral topics in

1:22

general. In monotheistic religions

1:24

and in Buddhism and in all

1:27

kinds of different philosophers' works across

1:29

time, people have had

1:32

bad things to say about

1:34

interest, and religions have

1:36

forbidden it in many cases, and they've described

1:38

it as being as bad as murder in

1:41

some cases, and we

1:44

see this repeated across cultures,

1:46

across time and across space, which

1:48

is really curious. But

1:51

within the religious invocations

1:55

against usury and

1:57

against interest, Rothbard argues there is

1:59

no... nothing in the Gospels of the

2:01

early fathers, despite their hostility to trade,

2:03

that can be construed as urging the

2:05

prohibition of usury. I'm

2:08

not entirely sure how much, how

2:11

accurate this is, but I'm going to take

2:13

Rothbard's words for it. And

2:15

the prohibition of usury first came in 325 AD

2:17

at the Council of Niseya, and then in

2:22

the fifth century, Pope Leo extended it to the

2:24

laity, and then Charlemagne in 789 was

2:30

the first secular legislative to ban usury.

2:34

Now these are not

2:36

exactly arguments, they are bans,

2:39

but in terms of arguments against usury,

2:42

Rothbard in the history of economic thought has

2:44

a good discussion of the evolution of this

2:46

argument. So Aristotle offered an argument saying that

2:50

usury is hated because its gain

2:52

comes from money itself and not from that for

2:54

the sake of which money was invented. For

2:57

money was brought into existence for the purpose of

2:59

exchange, but interest increases the amount of the

3:01

money itself. Consequently, this

3:03

form of the business of getting wealth

3:06

is of all forms the most contrary

3:08

to nature. This

3:10

isn't very compelling, and Rothbard and

3:12

many other economists have offered good

3:14

arguments against it. Just because

3:16

something was invented for one purpose doesn't mean it

3:18

can't be used for another purpose. And

3:21

the idea that just money

3:26

not having any use in something

3:28

else is somehow forbidden, a

3:31

lot of things get used for other things. So it's not

3:33

very convincing. Aquinas had

3:36

a convoluted argument against

3:38

interest, wherein he argued

3:42

that since money is like

3:44

food and that it is consumed when it is used,

3:46

it makes no sense to pay if you're

3:49

going to return it. If you're going to return

3:51

it, it's a consumable good, so you've already returned

3:54

the same thing. It makes sense

3:56

to charge rent on, in his opinion, things

3:58

that are not consumed like a house. house because

4:01

you return the house, but you don't consume it during

4:03

its use, so you have to pay a rent on

4:05

it. And that also doesn't make

4:08

a lot of sense because people can

4:10

charge prices for all kinds of

4:12

things. And when people charge prices in general,

4:14

they charge them based on subjective valuation of

4:16

the sum of all the

4:18

services that the good renders. So it's

4:21

not entirely convincing to say that people

4:23

shouldn't be able to charge for something

4:25

for which others are willingly paying. Another

4:29

argument is that it is maybe immoral to not

4:31

share risk for the lender and the borrower to

4:33

not share the risk equally because the borrower bears

4:35

the risk while the lender only shares in the

4:37

upside. But if this is immoral,

4:40

then why do borrowers accept it willingly?

4:43

Rothbard goes through a

4:45

lot of these arguments, and I

4:47

think the very powerful argument against

4:49

them is that people continue to

4:51

find ways to

4:54

introduce interest. So throughout the Middle Ages,

4:56

even though a lot of places had

4:58

banned interest, there were all kinds of

5:00

creative arrangements that merchants came up with

5:03

to introduce interest into the contract without

5:05

making it look to the church authorities

5:07

that this was interest. And

5:09

then Rothbard provides some of the arguments from

5:13

scholastics and Calvinist priests

5:15

and scholars on

5:17

the problem of

5:19

interest. And so Cardinal

5:21

Hosteianesis in the 13th century

5:25

introduced the concept of opportunity cost, that when

5:27

you're lending money, you're forgoing

5:29

the ability to make returns on investments

5:31

yourself. And for that, people

5:35

require compensation for lending. In

5:37

the 15th century, there was a complete

5:40

refutation of the arguments, according to Rothbard.

5:43

And then there was the argument

5:45

that liquidity has its value, and

5:47

so forgoing liquidity requires

5:50

the person charging. John

5:52

Calvin argued that money is not sterile.

5:55

And that's contrary to Aristotle, because it generates profits through trade.

5:58

And then Rothbard said, the

6:00

Dutch Calvinist Claude Sommes put the final

6:03

nail in the coffin. Money lending is

6:05

a business like any other and so

6:07

just like people spend time and effort

6:09

in order to provide apples

6:11

or wheat or meat for the market,

6:14

people will also spend time and effort to

6:16

try and provide capital for the market and

6:18

so they require compensation for it. And

6:21

Rothbard says on Sommes

6:23

he did make the important theoretical point

6:25

however that as in any other part

6:27

of the market if the

6:29

number of users multiplies, the price of

6:32

money or interest will be driven down

6:34

by the competition so that

6:36

if one doesn't like high interest rates,

6:39

the more users the better. And

6:42

I think this is a very interesting line

6:44

of thought which we're going to get back

6:46

to later in this discussion. Now

6:48

in this end of the 18th century

6:51

Jeremy Bentham provided

6:53

the argument, the liberal argument

6:56

against or for interest lending

6:58

which is that if some man of sane

7:01

mind acting freely wants to enter

7:03

into a particular arrangement with money

7:06

there is no good argument

7:09

for stopping him if he sees that this is

7:11

beneficial to them. But until here

7:13

we see that we haven't really

7:15

formulated a precise

7:19

economic argument for interest. They've

7:21

refuted, all the economists that

7:23

we've seen they've refuted some of

7:25

the fallacious arguments against interest. They've

7:27

introduced the liberal argument which is people

7:30

should be free to do what they

7:32

want but there was no clear explanation

7:34

of why is it economically that

7:38

people engage in interest lending.

7:40

And for that we have

7:42

to wait till Turgot, Bombarek

7:44

and Frank Fetter introduced the

7:47

time preference explanation for interest. So Turgot was

7:49

the first to bring this up according to

7:51

Rothbard. He introduced the concept of

7:53

subjective valuation to the question. And

7:55

so the subjective value of the monetary sums is

7:58

what matters and not the quantity of interest. of

8:00

metal involved. That was, I think, the key

8:02

breakthrough into Gold's work. That it's perfectly

8:05

normal for somebody to prefer a smaller sum

8:07

of coins today, 100 coins today, over 110

8:13

coins next year, because valuation

8:15

is not inherent in the

8:17

physical coins. Valuation

8:19

is subjective. And so it might be the case

8:21

that I value 100 points today more than I

8:24

value 110 coins next year. And

8:26

so therefore, I'm conducting a beneficial

8:28

trade for myself when I trade

8:31

taking 100 coins today, and then I

8:33

pay 110 coins next

8:35

year. So the value, this

8:38

is basically the concept of time

8:40

preference. People value a satisfaction today

8:42

more than they value the same

8:44

satisfaction in the future. So once

8:46

you accept that value is subjective,

8:48

and that people value things subjectively, it's

8:51

perfectly normal to understand that they would

8:53

value a smaller sum, more

8:55

than a larger sum. And that's why they take

8:57

the loan. That's why they accept the loan. And

9:00

time preference later on, Baumberg and Frank

9:03

Fetter and Austrian economists will elaborate on

9:05

this concept more. And I

9:07

think it is, it's a category

9:09

of human action. It's something that pervades

9:12

all of human actions in that we

9:14

always prefer the present to the future.

9:17

Present is certain, the future is uncertain.

9:19

The future can only come by surviving

9:22

the present. So the present's needs

9:24

are always more pressing. There's no future if

9:26

you don't survive to get to the future.

9:28

So you have to prioritize the present to

9:31

prioritize your survival. And the present

9:33

is where all the senses experience life, it's where you

9:35

experience pleasure and pain, and all of the

9:38

sensations that drivers toward action.

9:41

So time preference is always positive. But

9:44

it varies between people and it varies

9:46

in the same person at different times.

9:48

So your time preference is constantly changing

9:50

throughout life, due to the conditions and

9:52

the circumstances of life. But

9:55

the fact that the valuation differs between

9:58

people, the fact that people more

12:00

than I value the money today. And the reason

12:02

for that is that I have a lower discounting

12:04

of the future than he does. So he might

12:06

be in a position where he needs the money

12:09

right now because he's got an emergency. So he's

12:11

got a much higher time preference, so he's willing

12:13

to pay a sum that would allow me and

12:16

justify for me the choice of forgoing the

12:18

liquidity for that period of time.

12:21

So this then creates a lending

12:23

market because it's not just individuals trading together,

12:25

then there becomes a lending market, which is

12:27

like a market for time. And

12:29

that market will then have a general

12:32

market interest rate, which is

12:34

the sum, if you want, of all of the

12:37

market, the origin of the interests and the

12:39

contribution of the people. And as Hoppe describes

12:42

it in Democracy, the God that Failed, this

12:45

market-determined interest rate is the aggregate sum

12:47

of all individual time preference rates reflecting

12:50

the social rate of time preference

12:52

and equilibrating social savings, i.e.

12:54

the supply of present goods offered for

12:56

exchange against future goods, and

12:59

social investment, i.e. the demand

13:01

for present goods thought

13:04

capable of yielding future returns. So

13:08

the time preference of people is

13:10

what shapes the market interest rate.

13:12

So market interest rates have their

13:14

origin in human action, and in

13:16

particular in the discounting that humans

13:18

place on the future. And

13:21

so as Rothbard elaborates in

13:23

Man, Economy and State, the

13:25

function of the capitalist in the market

13:28

economy is a time function. Their income

13:30

is precisely an income representing the agio

13:32

of present as compared to future goods.

13:35

This interest income then is not derived from

13:37

the concrete heterogeneous capital goods, but from the

13:39

generalized investment of time. And

13:41

this is the essence of the Austrian

13:44

time preference theory of interest, in

13:46

that it's not the productivity of goods which gives the

13:49

interest income. The interest income is the

13:51

discounting of the future. And so by

13:53

forgoing the present in order to receive

13:56

a repayment

13:58

in the future, And

18:00

so therefore, they're always going to find a way

18:02

because it's mutually beneficial for both parties to get

18:04

into it. Now, what

18:07

does it mean when we say that

18:09

interest rates are determined by time preference? But we

18:11

know, and Professor Oppa

18:13

describes it also in Democracy with

18:16

God that Tales, we know interest

18:18

rates historically have been declining. What does

18:20

that mean? As

18:22

Professor Oppa says, it's a

18:24

tendency toward falling interest rate

18:26

characterizes mankind's super-secular trend

18:28

of development. Whereas

18:30

high or rising minimum interest rates

18:33

indicate periods of generally low or

18:35

declining living standards, the

18:38

overriding opposite tendency toward low and

18:40

falling interest rates reflects mankind's overall

18:42

progress, its advance

18:44

from barbarism to civilization. Historically,

18:47

we see that time preference

18:50

declines in periods of declining,

18:52

of increasing prosperity. People's time

18:54

preference declines, so they save

18:57

more because we save more,

18:59

capital becomes more abundant, because we have

19:01

more capital, we're able to invest more,

19:03

productivity goes up, our ability to provide

19:05

for the future increases, and

19:07

that all reduces our time preference.

19:10

So prosperity and civilization,

19:13

as Professor Oppa describes

19:15

it, is what initiates the process of,

19:18

sorry, declining time preference is what initiates

19:21

the process of civilization. We can think

19:23

of civilization as the decline in time

19:25

preference. So then, the question

19:28

also raised in Democracy with God

19:31

that Failed, with this

19:33

historical backdrop and in accordance with economic

19:35

theory then, it should be

19:37

expected that 20th century interest rates would

19:39

be still lower than 19th century interest

19:41

rates. But

19:43

that is not the case. Interest rates

19:45

were the lowest in history recorded at

19:48

the beginning of the 20th century, around 2.5%. That

19:52

was the interest rate at the Bank of

19:54

England. So this was the lowest interest rate that

19:56

humanity had ever seen at 2.5%. And

20:00

if civilizational progress had continued in

20:02

the 20th century, you

20:04

would have expected that rate to decline. Now

20:06

it did not. And as

20:09

Professor Hoppe says, you can

20:12

only explain that by saying the character of

20:14

the population must have changed. People on the

20:16

average must have lost in moral and intellectual

20:19

strength and become more

20:21

present oriented. Indeed, this appears

20:23

to be the case. I think anybody who's been

20:25

familiar with the 20th century would argue

20:27

that there must have been some element of rise

20:30

in time preference. And I think

20:32

that's reflected in the interest rates. And

20:35

Professor Hoppe focuses on the role of

20:37

democracy on that. And I think that's

20:39

a very good point. And

20:41

I like to focus on the role of

20:43

fiat money and the value on the money that is

20:45

constantly being devalued because the money is declining in its

20:47

value. It doesn't

20:51

provide people a good mechanism for saving

20:53

for the future. So people's ability to

20:55

provide for their future becomes more difficult.

20:57

So the future becomes more uncertain. So

20:59

people start discounting the future more. I

21:03

think this and democracy are, of

21:05

course, related explanations because it was democracy

21:08

that gave us fiat money. And it's

21:10

fiat money that gave us democracy. It's a

21:12

chicken and egg problem. But

21:15

the end result of

21:17

this is there's been

21:19

a rise in time preference. The time preference

21:21

has been rising. So

21:24

this introduces a very interesting question.

21:27

What would happen if time preference continued to

21:29

decline from the beginning of the 20th century

21:31

until today? What would happen if time preference

21:33

had continued to decline? Imagine if we hadn't

21:36

had the horrible things of the 20th

21:38

century happen. It's a

21:40

very interesting question. It's so interesting that it

21:42

is actually my next book, The

21:45

Gold Standard. It's an

21:47

economic fictional book written at

21:50

the end of the 20th century in which

21:52

fiat money dies in 1915. And

21:54

the world goes back to the gold

21:56

standard throughout the 20th century. So

21:59

to try and imagine what would happen if time because

26:00

over time, money is the scarcest

26:02

good. It's the good that's being produced in the lowest quantities.

26:06

And therefore, it's the good that is going to

26:08

be appreciating most

26:10

over time. So simply holding onto money

26:13

provides you an appreciation. But

26:16

holding onto money also involves a cost

26:18

of storage and risk of damage

26:21

or theft or loss. So

26:24

lending the money allows you to reap the

26:26

benefit from its appreciation. If you get it

26:28

back at 0%, you reap the benefit from

26:30

the appreciation, but you don't

26:33

pay the cost of the storage of money. So

26:37

this would mean a nominal 0%

26:39

interest rate. And

26:41

one way of thinking of it is that

26:44

if capital is abundant, if capital is very

26:46

abundant, then zero is the ultimate end price

26:48

for capital. So the price approaches zero, doesn't

26:50

quite get to zero because time preference is

26:52

never zero, time preference

26:55

is always positive. But

26:57

it approaches zero, and then because the cost

26:59

of storing money is larger than zero, then

27:01

it doesn't really need to go to zero,

27:04

because the nominal interest rate will just still

27:06

be zero, and

27:10

the real rate will be positive.

27:13

So if time preference is very low for

27:15

everyone, then there

27:17

is no market in time valuation. So

27:20

if you understand the economic argument for interest,

27:22

it is that there is a differential in

27:24

time preference, and it's the differential in time

27:26

preference that creates the market

27:28

in interest, which is the market in valuation

27:31

of time. But if everybody's

27:33

time preference is so low that their

27:35

original interest is lower than the cost

27:37

of holding capital, then there's

27:40

no market to be had in valuations of

27:42

time. Everybody has a very, very

27:44

low time preference, and so the

27:48

distinctions in time preference are very

27:51

tiny, that the lending just happens at the 0%

27:53

rate, because

27:56

it's better than the cost of

27:58

holding capital. I

36:00

think where the market interest rates, I

36:02

guess how they might have behaved differently. So

36:06

I think it's very difficult to

36:09

pass judgment on interest rates

36:11

in a fiat environment because

36:14

they are the products of central planning. So

36:16

central banks basically decide the interest

36:18

rate because they buy and sell bonds

36:21

in a way that brings about the interest rate that

36:23

they want. And of course

36:25

they have a monopoly on the creation of the money or

36:27

at least they have a monopoly on the creation of the

36:30

money. So they can control

36:33

the money supply, they can control the price of money

36:36

and so they can impose an interest

36:38

rate on society effectively like situation

36:40

of price controls. So it's a

36:42

bit like trying to guess what

36:44

would be the price of potatoes

36:46

in a situation where you have a

36:49

central planning board for potatoes. It's

36:51

difficult to tell because if the central planning

36:53

board wasn't there then the entire potato industry

36:55

would be quite different. So the

36:58

answer that I would say is I wouldn't

37:03

have clear answers to

37:05

specific short term interest

37:07

rates. I wouldn't be able

37:09

to tell you that in the year 2000

37:11

interest rates should have been at

37:13

6% but they were actually at 3% or something of

37:16

the sort. I don't think you can

37:18

make something like that because it's a constantly

37:20

shifting policy that the central

37:22

bank follows. But I would imagine that

37:24

if there hadn't been a central bank

37:26

then you would have hard money so

37:28

you wouldn't have inflation and so people

37:31

would have a lot lower time preference

37:33

and so interest rates would likely decline

37:35

over time. And I

37:37

mean it depends on when in

37:39

your hypothetical you want to not have

37:42

the central banks. We just not

37:44

have central banks from day one or

37:46

we got rid of them last week. So

37:49

it depends but the longer we've

37:51

had without central banks then I

37:53

would imagine the lower

37:55

interest rate would go I think.

38:00

for Saif Diin. So

38:03

you are saying that in the process of

38:05

civilization the social time

38:07

preference rate falls and

38:11

at some point it reaches or

38:13

the nominal interest rate reaches a level where

38:15

it's equals the costs of

38:17

money storage and the risk of losing it.

38:21

But what about the risk premium and

38:24

the nominal interest rate? Would that not

38:27

prevent ever falling the nominal interest

38:29

rate to the level of

38:31

the cost of holding money? I

38:37

think there is a risk premium on lending

38:40

the money. There's also a risk premium on

38:42

keeping the money. So it's entirely

38:44

conceivable that the risk also declines.

38:47

So there's the cost of holding the money and the risk

38:50

of holding the money and then there's a

38:52

cost of lending it. Now with time and

38:54

as time preference drops you would

38:56

expect that the risk of default and the risk of

39:01

taking the money and running away would also

39:03

keep declining over time because people are lower

39:05

time preference more and more and more likely to

39:07

commit to their contracts. So

39:10

I'd still think the

39:12

more we lower our time preference

39:15

eventually the time preference needs

39:17

to go below the cost of storage.

39:19

Thank you. Something more to add to

39:21

the interest question. If you look at

39:23

the components of nominal interest and low

39:26

time preference and hard money certainly will

39:28

lead to the disappearance of the purchasing

39:30

power premium. Maybe not

39:32

so sure the terms of trade premium that

39:34

Rothbard came up with and one

39:36

thing that will not disappear is the

39:38

risk premium if you see it as

39:41

the perceived risk of not being paid

39:43

back. So I think there's not only

39:45

low time preference and hard

39:47

money needed but also trust. I

39:51

think you have to add trust

39:53

in the picture societal trust to

39:55

get that component to zero and

39:57

I would suggest that Guido's theory

39:59

of is there probably

40:01

a bit of a better fit? Guido's

40:06

theory of origin interest, because you gave

40:08

the example of giving a zero interest

40:10

loan to family and friends. And

40:13

I don't think that's only explainable or easy

40:16

or best explainable by low time preference.

40:18

I think Guido's suggestion that it may

40:20

be due to less

40:22

of a spread between means and ends, meaning

40:25

that it can be an end in

40:27

itself for you to provide family and

40:29

friends without the premium is

40:31

a better measure, better explanation for that.

40:33

So I would try to take that

40:35

into account when figuring out how it

40:37

could drop to zero. And I

40:40

think there was a trust place again, an

40:42

important role. I

40:48

would say, yes, I think that's a good

40:50

point to include the trust component. But I

40:52

would say it's also proxied

40:55

if you want to buy time preference,

40:57

because the lower time preference, the

41:00

more trustworthy people are. And

41:03

I would say

41:06

that ultimately,

41:10

the more you accumulate cash balances,

41:12

the more the utility of a

41:14

cash balance diminishes. I

41:17

should have perhaps specified this in detail. But

41:19

the utility of money is the thing that

41:22

has the least diminishing marginal utility, because

41:25

you can exchange it easier for everything else. But

41:28

utility still diminishes. Your

41:30

first dollar is not as valuable as when you go

41:33

from 100 million dollars to 100 million dollars in one

41:35

dollar. So

41:37

the first dollar is obviously much more valuable. So the

41:39

marginal utility of money diminishes. And

41:42

after a while, the more money you accumulate, you

41:46

see the benefit from diversification away from

41:48

holding the money yourself, because then if

41:50

your money gets compromised or stolen, all

41:53

of it gets compromised or stolen. But

41:55

you could diversify by lending to others. So

41:59

you would see that. how

42:01

the marginal utility of lending

42:03

can be positive for the case that you mentioned,

42:05

which is that you get

42:08

some value from lending to others at

42:10

no interest, but also to diversify from

42:12

having all of your money in one

42:14

place.

Unlock more with Podchaser Pro

  • Audience Insights
  • Contact Information
  • Demographics
  • Charts
  • Sponsor History
  • and More!
Pro Features