Episode Transcript
Transcripts are displayed as originally observed. Some content, including advertisements may have changed.
Use Ctrl + F to search
0:00
You're listening to the Stephen Wolfram
0:02
podcast, an exploration of thoughts and
0:04
ideas from the founder and CEO
0:07
of Wolfram Research, creator of Wolfram
0:09
Alpha and the Wolfram Language. In
0:12
this ongoing Q&A series, Stephen answers
0:14
questions from his live stream audience
0:16
about science and technology. This session
0:19
was originally broadcast on March 7th,
0:21
2025. Let's have a listen. Hello
0:25
everyone, welcome to another
0:27
episode of science and
0:29
technology Q&A for kids
0:31
and others. So I see a whole
0:34
bunch of questions saved up here. Hmm,
0:36
this is one that's, well, okay,
0:38
one from Atari. Can you talk
0:41
about Lambda calculus? I'll try.
0:43
This would be easier if I
0:45
was allowing myself to show you
0:47
things on the computer and so
0:49
on, but let me try and
0:52
give some. some background and try
0:54
and explain this. So,
0:56
uh, Lambda calculus is an
0:58
idea from 1935, actually, that
1:01
was one of the different
1:03
possible models for
1:05
what computation might consist of.
1:08
So, these days, you
1:10
know, we use computers
1:12
all the time, we have some
1:14
idea of what it means to
1:17
do a computation. One can think
1:19
of a computation as being something
1:21
where you define certain rules and then
1:23
those rules get automatically applied many
1:25
times. That's what the computation
1:28
is. Back in the early part of the 20th
1:30
century, there was an attempt to
1:32
particularly take all the things that sort of
1:35
happen in mathematics and say what's
1:37
in common between all these different
1:39
things one does in mathematics, whether
1:42
one's doing geometry or whether one's
1:44
doing algebra or whether one's doing
1:46
arithmetic arithmetic arithmetic. What is the
1:48
kind of common infrastructure, the common
1:51
raw material from which one can
1:53
build up all those different areas
1:55
of mathematics? And people had
1:57
a bunch of different schemes for...
2:00
what that might consist of.
2:02
The fundamental thing people
2:04
imagine doing is just write down
2:06
sort of a symbolic expression, make
2:08
something that has, you know, things
2:11
like an F of X or
2:13
F of G of X or
2:15
whatever. These are things where we're
2:18
not necessarily saying what F and
2:20
GDR, they're just kind of a
2:22
structure. Now, for example, when we
2:25
have an algebraic expression, like
2:27
something like 2x plus
2:29
y squared. We can think
2:32
of that, and this is what
2:34
we do with morphmal language, as
2:36
a times of 2 and x.
2:39
There's a plus outside the whole
2:41
thing, and then there's a power
2:43
of y and 2, whatever I
2:45
said. And we can think of
2:47
it as a symbolic expression
2:50
plus of times of x of
2:52
2, of 2, of power. of Y and
2:54
2 or whatever. Well, the idea, the big
2:56
idea, was that sort of all these
2:59
different things that come
3:01
up in math, whether
3:03
you're representing arithmetic, algebra,
3:05
geometry, group theory, other kinds
3:07
of things, could all be
3:09
represented in this kind of
3:12
symbolic expression way. It was kind
3:14
of an idea that sort of came
3:16
into existence, I would say, in the
3:18
late 1800s, 1880s, 1890s, and so on,
3:21
and then people as a chap. David
3:23
Hilbert who pushed this idea, Whitehead and
3:25
Russell kind of pushed this idea, they
3:27
kind of wanted to, they thought of
3:30
it as being, sort of derived everything
3:32
from logic, not that they, although implicitly
3:34
they were also using the symbolic
3:37
expression idea. Now I have to
3:39
say that, that I kind of
3:41
coddened onto the symbolic expression idea
3:43
in the end of the 1970s when
3:45
I was designing the sort of forerunner
3:47
of what's now often language. and it's
3:49
all based on everything that I've
3:52
done in sort of our computational
3:54
language and so on is all
3:56
based on the symbolic expression idea
3:58
which really dates originally from the
4:00
early part of the 20th century, and
4:02
it had some uses in the intervening
4:04
years, but what we've been able to
4:06
build the kind of tower of capability
4:09
that we've been able to build in
4:11
the Wolfman language is certainly something I
4:13
hadn't imagined one could build such a
4:15
tall tower, but it's all based on
4:18
this idea of symbolic expressions. Okay, how
4:20
does this relate to Lamba calculus?
4:22
Well, you have these symbolic expressions.
4:25
and they might represent some
4:27
algebraic formula, they might
4:29
represent some piece of geometry,
4:31
whatever else. What are you going
4:34
to do with them? You have to have
4:36
some kind of way in which they
4:38
kind of do operations. So for
4:40
example, if you had a piece
4:43
of that symbolic expression that represented
4:46
two plus two. You want it to
4:48
be the case that that
4:50
gets evaluated to four. You
4:52
have to have something which
4:54
is kind of animating this
4:56
symbolic expression, making it do things.
4:58
And that's, so you have these
5:01
rules that define what to do.
5:03
If you see a piece of
5:05
symbolic expression that looks like this,
5:07
what are you going to do with it?
5:09
The first, well, there were, you could
5:11
think of logic as being a little
5:14
bit like that. If you say P
5:16
and P. you can transform that, you
5:18
can transform that to just
5:20
P. Just like if you say,
5:22
you know, you said P plus P,
5:24
where plus is an arithmetic addition,
5:26
then that's equal to two times
5:28
P and so on. Well, kind
5:31
of the question was, what's the
5:33
sort of general way to
5:35
represent those transformations? There
5:37
were several different ideas.
5:39
First one, a studio trap
5:41
called Moses-Schhenfinkle in 1920.
5:44
was the idea of
5:46
combinators. They're very, very abstract.
5:48
They're very hard to understand. I
5:50
wrote a book about them a
5:52
few years ago. They are, even
5:54
100 years later, they're very
5:56
hard to understand. And people
5:58
didn't understand. them then
6:00
and it sort of didn't really
6:02
engage in and get a lot
6:04
of people to pay attention. There
6:07
was a chap called Emmel Post
6:09
who started talking about essentially
6:11
string rewriting systems where it's
6:13
kind of a bit like
6:15
a text editor where you
6:17
say if you have a
6:19
string that goes, you know,
6:21
A-A-A-B-B-B-B-B-B, you should replace that
6:23
with B-A or something. That
6:25
was another idea that was
6:28
from 2021. Well, there was
6:30
another idea from 1931,
6:32
which was called general
6:34
cursive functions, which were
6:36
Kurt Gertel used that
6:38
idea in proving Gertel's
6:41
theorem. And then in 1935,
6:43
Alonzo Church, mathematician
6:45
of Princeton, had the idea
6:47
of what he called Lander
6:50
calculus. And how to
6:52
explain Lander calculus? Lander
6:54
calculus is a way
6:57
of... describing kind of
6:59
transformations for symbolic
7:01
expressions. And the idea is
7:04
more or less this. So let's say
7:06
you say I have a function F,
7:08
and you're going to say F of
7:10
X is X squared. What does
7:12
that really mean? In Wolfram
7:14
language, the way that that would
7:16
be specified is F of X
7:19
blank, where blank is an underscore
7:21
character, colon equals X
7:24
squared. What does that mean? It
7:26
means there is a pattern of the
7:28
form F of any expression, that's the
7:31
blank. We're going to name it X. F
7:33
of any expression should be transformed
7:35
to that expression squared. So
7:38
that's kind of a way of thinking
7:40
about what a function is. It's
7:42
a thing where you have the
7:44
symbolic expression of the form F
7:46
of any expression, and that is
7:48
then transformed in the way
7:50
that I just specified. Okay, so that's
7:52
one view of sort of what
7:54
functions are. is there are things
7:56
that transform symbolic expressions to other
7:59
symbolic expressions. Okay, so the
8:01
lambda calculus idea is if
8:03
you've got something like F of
8:06
X is X squared, how do
8:08
you make a kind of pure anonymous
8:11
function that is what F
8:13
itself is in a sense? You've
8:15
said what F of X is
8:17
that it's X squared, but can
8:20
you just say what is F
8:22
itself without talking about the
8:24
X? And the idea is that
8:26
F itself is Landa of...
8:28
Let's call it Z. Z squared.
8:30
What does that mean? When we're
8:33
saying lambda of Z, one says,
8:35
we're going to expect something that's
8:37
going to be fed into that
8:39
Z slot, and we're going to
8:42
take that thing and square it.
8:44
And so the idea of a
8:46
lander expression, a pure function,
8:48
sometimes called an anonymous function,
8:51
because it doesn't have a
8:53
name, as it's not F.
8:55
It's what F. is what you can
8:57
think of as being the pure
8:59
F function. It's this thing that
9:02
says Landry of Z, which means
9:04
basically I'm expecting something,
9:07
I'm expecting something that's
9:09
going to be fed in Landry
9:12
of Z Z squared. So that
9:14
means I'm going to eat any
9:16
expression and I'm going to take
9:18
that expression and square
9:21
it. So that's a lambda function.
9:23
And the idea is that you
9:25
can write. sort of something you
9:27
can that that lambda function is
9:30
then reduced so if you say
9:32
land of z z squared and
9:34
then you say apply that to x
9:36
plus one let's say the it'll
9:38
bind the x plus one to
9:41
the z sort of eat the
9:43
x plus one and turn the
9:45
result to x plus one squared
9:47
so this sort of a reduction
9:49
rule that's some it's usually
9:52
called beta reduction that
9:54
essentially takes the pure lambda
9:56
expression and you're feeding it things,
9:58
you're applying it. that lander expression
10:01
as a pure function, two
10:03
things, and then it is being reduced
10:05
to the result of feeding that thing
10:07
into its bound variable and then
10:09
turning it into the body of
10:12
lander expression. This is hard to
10:14
explain. I probably shouldn't have attempted
10:16
this without actually typing things on
10:18
a computer. But to give you
10:21
sort of the flavor of it,
10:23
a lander expression is a pure
10:25
function, a disembodied function, a
10:27
disembodied function that has no
10:29
name. It is just a thing that says
10:31
I am expecting to eat an expression
10:33
and this is what I will do
10:36
with that expression if I am fed it.
10:38
And the point is that you
10:40
can write programs and things as
10:42
big collections of lander functions. And
10:44
then the running of the program
10:46
is just the lander function doing
10:49
the transformations that lander functions
10:51
do. And you can, it gets
10:53
very kind of funky because you
10:55
can have sort of very pure
10:58
lander expressions. that aren't really applied
11:00
to anything, they're just doing reductions
11:02
like beta reduction by being applied
11:04
to other lander expressions. And actually
11:07
I was just studying this recently,
11:09
the kind of ruelliology of lander
11:11
expressions, and trying to understand if
11:13
you have just pure lander expressions,
11:16
you can have a situation where you basically
11:18
can the lander expression will sort
11:20
of eat another lander expression and
11:23
produce another lander expression, it will
11:25
keep going. It'll never stop. It'll
11:27
never stop. It's a, or even
11:29
it will even grow and
11:31
it will produce more, it's
11:33
eating lander expressions, it's producing
11:35
lander expressions, it's just producing
11:37
this bigger and bigger structure.
11:40
So those are, those are sort
11:42
of obscure pure computation ideas, but
11:44
the main idea is it's this
11:46
way of sort of abstracting the
11:48
function out of the sort of
11:50
the pure function. If F of
11:52
X is X squared, what is
11:54
F itself itself itself itself? You
11:56
can think of it as a pure function.
12:00
Things like that are very useful.
12:02
I mean in Wolfram language,
12:04
we call it the function function.
12:06
It is a function whose name is function.
12:09
It gets written with an ampersand and
12:11
things. It has a nice short
12:13
form, but it is the function function.
12:15
And you might say, well, why do I
12:17
want a function function? Well, then
12:20
it turns out to be very, very
12:22
useful. I would say that in people
12:24
learning Wolfram language and
12:26
so on, one... At first, people will say,
12:28
I don't need anything that abstract. I
12:30
don't need that pure function thing. It's
12:33
way too abstract. And they don't
12:35
use it at first. And then at some
12:37
point when they've sort of by hand
12:39
done the things for which pure
12:41
functions are really useful, eventually you can
12:43
show them a pure function and it'll
12:46
be like, aha, okay, now I get
12:48
it, now I can automate, simplify a
12:50
lot of things I've done in the past.
12:52
A typical example is you want to
12:54
apply some operation. to lots of the
12:56
same operation, to lots of different things.
12:59
So let's say you have a bunch of
13:01
images and you're going to invert the colors,
13:03
find the edges, etc., etc., etc. What you
13:05
want to do is you might say, well,
13:08
I'll write a function that does all those
13:10
things and then you'd map that function over
13:12
all those images. But you might say, I
13:14
don't want to bother to write out that
13:16
function and write F of X, blank, colon
13:19
equals, and then that definition of edge
13:21
detection of edge detection, whatever. I
13:23
just want to put something to
13:25
put something in. that stands for
13:27
that function. And that's what
13:29
you can do. You can just
13:31
say something like, you know, edge
13:34
detective, hash sign, and then ampersand,
13:36
that thing is a pure function
13:38
which can now be served the
13:41
role of a function that can
13:43
be applied to all those images.
13:45
So that's kind of the idea,
13:47
and that's how it ends up
13:49
being useful. Very different
13:52
question here. asks any
13:54
thoughts on numerology? Actually, let
13:56
me just see if there
13:58
are more comments on them. Okay,
14:00
well, what is numerology?
14:03
Numerology tends
14:05
to be, oh, I noticed
14:07
that this thing in the
14:10
world, like the mass of
14:12
the muon divided by
14:14
the mass of the
14:16
electron, which is roughly
14:19
206, that really that
14:21
that ratio is actually
14:24
very close to the
14:26
square root of pie
14:28
divided by seven to
14:30
the power of three, who knows
14:32
what, something that's just pure
14:35
numbers. So numerology is the
14:37
real, is the, is sort
14:39
of the, the correspondence between
14:41
things that are purely made
14:44
of numbers and things that
14:46
you see kind of in the
14:48
real world. That's the most common
14:50
use of that term.
14:52
Occasionally there's kind of
14:55
within mathematics numerology. People
14:57
notice that's that. there is
14:59
some kind of coincidence that,
15:01
oh, this series of numbers
15:03
that appear in this mathematical
15:05
problem are the same series
15:08
of numbers that appear in
15:10
that mathematical problem. There have
15:12
been a number of cases,
15:14
most notably in studying large
15:16
finite groups and things, where
15:18
that kind of numerology has
15:20
paid off, where noticing in
15:22
mathematics that this sequence is
15:25
the same as that other
15:27
one, that then a connection
15:29
was found between the source of
15:31
those sequences. Numerology has
15:33
a much less good history
15:35
in natural science and even
15:38
worse history probably in
15:40
kind of more human
15:42
oriented areas. It's kind of,
15:44
you know, there are many examples
15:47
of people trying this. It's
15:49
really basically, as I'm thinking
15:51
about it's ever worked. One
15:54
thing that's often the target of
15:56
this is the thing of the
15:58
fine structure constant, which is a... characterization
16:00
of the strength of
16:02
electromagnetic forces, it happens
16:05
to be dimensionless. It's just a
16:07
number. It's roughly one over 137.
16:09
And people say, well we should
16:11
be able to just derive this
16:13
from something lower level if we
16:15
have a fundamental theory of physics,
16:17
for example, we should just be
16:19
able to derive the fine structure
16:21
constant. And one day I would hope that
16:23
our theories of theory of physics will be
16:26
able to do that. It's worth realizing,
16:28
just sort of a footnote to
16:30
that story, is that the fine
16:33
structure constant as a
16:35
strength of electromagnetic forces
16:37
really depends on the observer
16:40
observing those forces. The value
16:42
of one over 137 is only
16:44
really correct for an observer that's
16:46
operating in a sense at very
16:48
low energy. An observer who in
16:50
the uncertainty principle kind of relates
16:53
to length scales. an observer who
16:55
is kind of measuring electromagnetic forces
16:57
on a very large length scale,
16:59
as you probe them on shorter
17:01
length scales, the effective value of
17:03
the of the fine structure constant
17:05
changes. So it's a little bit
17:07
tricky to just sort of say,
17:10
oh, well, we should have the
17:12
fine structure constant and just fall
17:14
out of the theory. It's the thing
17:16
that falls out of the theory has to
17:18
be something whose value depends on the observer
17:20
who's observing the thing. But in any
17:22
case, there's sort of a an effort. to,
17:25
it's not been a good story of
17:27
people trying to find, you know, oh,
17:29
it's really square to pie, terms this,
17:31
and the other. Now, you know, it's
17:34
worth trying to understand
17:36
the sort of theory of numerology.
17:38
I will tell you something
17:40
that if you type into
17:43
Wolfmalfa, some just random number,
17:45
1.284643, whatever, it will have a
17:47
pod that comes out that lists
17:50
possible closed forms. It will tell
17:52
you... what ratios of pies and
17:54
things like this are close to
17:56
the number you typed in. Now it has
17:58
a bit of a tradeoff. because you
18:00
could get something that's exactly the
18:03
number you've typed in, but it's
18:05
a sum of eight powers of
18:07
pie divided by lots of powers
18:10
of e and so on. It
18:12
could be a really
18:14
complicated formula. It's sort
18:16
of completely unsurprising that
18:18
there is a really
18:20
complicated formula that represents, you
18:23
know, the six digits you
18:25
typed in of that number,
18:27
plus seven over a hundred.
18:29
and that's a nice in terms
18:32
of whole numbers formula. It's
18:34
just not telling one very
18:36
much because that really is just
18:38
the number you put in. Now, if
18:40
the number that I put in was
18:42
3.1.4.159, then it might be telling me
18:45
something to say that's just pie.
18:47
I could say that number is 3 plus
18:49
1 over 10 plus 4 over 100
18:51
plus whatever, but that's a kind
18:54
of a long description of the
18:56
number. The thing that's interesting is
18:58
if there's a short description
19:00
of the number in terms
19:02
of things like pie or whatever
19:04
else. And in a sense, the
19:06
mission of numerology, I suppose, is to
19:09
say, is there a small formula for
19:11
all the digits that you know of
19:13
that number? It's kind of a thing
19:15
where it's like asking, you know, you
19:17
can think of that powers of pie
19:20
or whatever else, as like a program
19:22
for making the number. And so essentially
19:24
numerology is this question of is there
19:26
a short program that makes my number?
19:28
I can clearly have a program that's
19:31
about the same length as the number
19:33
itself that just writes down the number,
19:35
but is there a short program that
19:37
makes the number? Now, even that's a
19:39
tricky thing to say, because the question
19:42
of what kinds of operations can be
19:44
in that program. For example, I talked
19:46
about pie and so on. People have
19:48
heard of pie, but how about if I talk about,
19:50
I don't know the... Well, next level
19:52
of obscurity would be the
19:55
Euler-Masharoni constant, where another level
19:57
would be, you know, the Madelang sum
19:59
of some... These are all kinds of
20:01
things that can be thought
20:03
of as mathematical constants, but
20:05
they have an increasing level
20:08
of obscurity to them. And so then
20:10
you have the tradeoff of, well,
20:12
you know, how many pies is
20:14
one Madeline constant equivalent to? Because
20:17
if I introduce obscure enough constants,
20:19
then again, I'm kind of,
20:21
you know, for example, I
20:23
could just invent a constant
20:25
that is... the my personal constant that is
20:27
the number I just typed in and
20:29
then I've got a very short description
20:32
but you still you don't know what
20:34
my personal constant is that you have
20:36
to have a whole sort of chain
20:38
of knowledge of that so in a sense
20:40
sort of the question is if you have
20:43
a certain language for describing your
20:45
number that might include pies square roots
20:47
things like that how small can
20:49
the description of your number be
20:51
and that's a reasonable question
20:53
There are clearly, if you
20:55
think about all possible numbers,
20:58
most of them can't have
21:00
short descriptions because those short
21:02
descriptions are much fewer in
21:04
number than all the possible
21:06
numbers with all their digits. But
21:08
this question of sort of how
21:10
much is a pie versus, you
21:12
know, what's the effective sort of
21:14
description length of saying I've got
21:17
a pie? as opposed to I've got
21:19
a Madelan constant. Interesting question, not
21:21
obvious what the answer should be,
21:23
like 15 years ago when we
21:26
were building that capability
21:28
in Wolfram Alpha, what we did
21:30
was this. We looked at basically
21:32
all kind of easily available
21:34
math papers, academic papers. And
21:36
we simply say, how often
21:38
do these constants appear? Pie
21:41
appears all over the place.
21:43
The Euler-Mascheroni constant, much less
21:45
frequently. The Madelone constant, even
21:47
much less frequently. And then what
21:50
we said was, let's say that
21:52
the sort of effective information content
21:54
of saying it's pie is much smaller
21:56
in proportion to how much more
21:59
frequently. it appears in mathematical
22:01
literature. Like if I say
22:03
it's pie, I probably not
22:05
have to tell you anymore. If
22:07
I say it's the Smith constant,
22:09
I'm going to have to define
22:12
what I mean by the Smith
22:14
constant. And so that was sort
22:16
of a way of getting a
22:18
proxy for sort of what the
22:20
effective amount of information associated with
22:22
saying it's constant such and
22:25
such. having thought about that,
22:27
you know, you're kind of in this
22:29
position of saying, well, if I've got
22:31
some number that I just measured in
22:34
the world, you know, how small a program
22:36
can I make for that number? And
22:38
is that significant and
22:40
so on? And if I have that
22:42
small program for the number, can
22:44
I imagine a mechanism by
22:46
which that number would be the value
22:48
that it is? Let me give you
22:51
an example within mathematics.
22:53
If you look at pair of
22:55
numbers, let's say 12 and 4,
22:57
okay, 12 and 8, okay, 12 and
22:59
8 are not relatively prime,
23:01
what does that mean?
23:04
It means there is a divisor of
23:06
8, 8 is 2 times 4, 12
23:08
is 4 times 3, okay, the 4
23:10
is uncommon between those. So
23:13
those numbers have a divisor
23:15
in common, they are not
23:18
relatively prime. If we were
23:20
to talk about... Let's say, oh
23:22
gosh, let me not fail my
23:24
arithmetic here. Let's talk about
23:26
10 and what's a good example.
23:29
10 and 21, okay? 10
23:31
is 2 times 5, 21 is 7
23:33
times 3. I'm so proud of myself
23:35
I'm now beginning to know
23:38
my multiplication tables. I didn't
23:40
know that when I was
23:42
a kid, I've gradually learned
23:45
them over the course of
23:47
my life. But in any case,
23:49
10. and 21 are relatively prime
23:51
because they have no factors in common.
23:53
Okay, so I can ask the question. Let's
23:55
say I try a whole bunch of
23:57
different numbers and I ask what's the...
24:00
chance that two numbers are
24:02
relatively prime. And the answer,
24:04
I'll get some number, I
24:06
forget what the exact number
24:08
is, but I go in
24:10
to get more and more
24:12
and more digits. And then
24:14
maybe I type it into
24:16
Wolfram Alpha and I say,
24:18
what is this number? It's
24:20
gonna say it's six over
24:22
pie squared. Well, that turns
24:24
out to be a piece
24:26
of numerology that works, because
24:28
it really is six over
24:30
pie squared, and there is
24:32
a mathematical argument. for why
24:34
it has to be six
24:36
of a pie squared. And
24:38
so that's a case where
24:40
sort of the numerology works
24:42
out. And as I say,
24:44
sometimes it does in math.
24:46
I'll mention this question of
24:48
kind of numbers and kind
24:50
of how produceable is that
24:52
number. So let's say that
24:54
I've got a number and
24:56
it is it is produceable
24:58
as six over pie squared,
25:00
for example. I can imagine
25:02
that if I'm just looking
25:04
at all possible numbers, I
25:06
might type in six over
25:09
five square and that might
25:11
be the number I generate.
25:13
But let's say that you've
25:15
just got the number one
25:17
point seven, three, four, two,
25:19
six, five, four, three, seven,
25:21
four, three, seven, nine, one,
25:23
whatever. I don't think I'm
25:25
very good at generating random
25:27
digits, but it's just some
25:29
sort of randomly generated sequence
25:31
of digits. and it's really
25:33
a number that I'm very
25:35
unlikely to find. Is it
25:37
a number which whose chance
25:39
of occurring is about proportional
25:41
to 10 to the minus
25:43
the number of digits that
25:45
I've specified? So you might
25:47
say why would anybody care
25:49
about knowing whether a number
25:51
is produceable in that sense?
25:53
I'll give you an example.
25:55
Back in the early 1990s
25:57
there was a big disaster,
25:59
Intel, semiconductor company, had made
26:01
a the pantium chip with
26:03
the 856 microprocessor. Lots of
26:05
fanfare, exciting, fast, better, the
26:07
new technology microprocessor. Somebody noticed
26:09
that a particular set of
26:11
numbers, if you divided one
26:13
number by the other, you
26:15
got the wrong answer. The
26:18
Pentium chip just gave the
26:20
wrong answer for a particular
26:22
division of two particular numbers.
26:24
So then the question was,
26:26
how much does that matter?
26:28
If you were just picking
26:30
numbers at random based on
26:32
their digits, the chance of
26:34
hitting the number that was
26:36
one of these bug numbers
26:38
was incredibly low. I mean
26:40
ridiculously low to the point
26:42
where certainly wouldn't have happened
26:44
in human history with people
26:46
running Pentium chips all the
26:48
time. But if that number
26:50
was a produceable number that
26:52
turned out to be really
26:54
it's six over pie square
26:56
or something to enough digits,
26:58
then much bigger deal because
27:00
one could really imagine that
27:02
that number would actually show
27:04
up in practice. Turns out
27:06
so far as I could
27:08
ever tell the numbers that
27:10
led to the bug were
27:12
not produceable numbers. By the
27:14
way this term produceable number
27:16
I just invented that three
27:18
minutes ago or something it's
27:20
not a standard term in
27:22
the literature of mathematics and
27:24
so on. But I think
27:26
it's a good term for
27:29
this particular idea. That's sort
27:31
of an application of this,
27:33
that's sort of an inverse
27:35
numerology kind of question of,
27:37
oh, there is no simple
27:39
version of this number, so
27:41
we don't have to worry
27:43
as much about the fact
27:45
that there is a bug
27:47
in that case because the
27:49
chance that that number occurs
27:51
is really, really small. Well,
27:53
so that's a few comments
27:55
on numerality. I mentioned one
27:57
more thing. So think of
27:59
Benford's law. And it's one
28:01
of these things where it's
28:03
like, well, this is a
28:05
weird numerical numerical feature. So
28:07
if you can. kinds of
28:09
numbers that occur in practice,
28:11
like I don't know, the
28:13
market caps of public companies.
28:15
or the kinds of numbers
28:17
that you'd see on a
28:19
bank statement. And you ask
28:21
the following question. You say,
28:23
what's the first digit of
28:25
that number? Is it $131?
28:27
Is it $372? Just take
28:29
the one or the three
28:31
or whatever. Question is, do
28:33
all leading digits of numbers
28:35
occur with equal frequency? Well,
28:38
the answer is that in
28:40
most sort of practical numbers
28:42
that show up... in accounting
28:44
statements or whatever else, they
28:46
don't occur with equal frequency.
28:48
One is much more probable
28:50
than two and so on
28:52
going down to nine. It
28:54
turns out, so why is
28:56
that? Well, the reason is
28:58
that when you do mathematical
29:00
operations, the, in a sense,
29:02
the, the, what matters, what,
29:04
yeah, the, the, what matters,
29:06
is the logarithms of these
29:08
numbers are equally distributed, but
29:10
the numbers themselves are not.
29:12
And what happens, let's see
29:14
how to explain this. Well,
29:16
roughly, the point is that
29:18
if you're picking a number,
29:20
independent of its size, the
29:22
point is that numbers that
29:24
are... as you
29:26
reduce it to be a number that
29:29
you write out in terms of digits,
29:31
when you pick the number, sort of
29:33
independent of size, you're more likely to
29:35
land in that part of the digit
29:38
representation of the number that begins with
29:40
a one, and that begins with a
29:42
nine, and so on. It's kind of
29:44
a standard trick for trying to detect
29:47
fraud and accounting, for example. Just look
29:49
at all the numbers, and you just
29:51
say, well, if there are really a
29:53
lot of numbers that begin with a
29:56
nine, that are, you know, the amounts
29:58
of payables and things like this. that's
30:00
kind of fishy. And it's sort of
30:02
a common heuristic for that. It works,
30:04
Benford's law works for many kinds of
30:07
things. It works, I think, for the
30:09
powers of two. It doesn't happen
30:11
to work. That's in a pure
30:13
mathematics setting, not in a sort
30:15
of human world setting. I don't
30:17
think it works for primes, and I
30:20
don't think it works for some other
30:22
kinds of numbers. And it's an interesting
30:24
question, which there isn't really a great
30:26
answer to, of why it works. Anyway,
30:29
a few thoughts about
30:31
numerology. Oh boy, there's some
30:34
following questions here. Okay,
30:36
so Technic says that their
30:39
current favorite approximation
30:42
to a constant, in this case,
30:44
E, is some combination
30:46
of digits here. Wow, that's
30:49
interesting. That's
30:51
accurate. They claim to
30:53
18 septilian digits. That
30:55
seems very. Hard to believe
30:58
to me, but that's an
31:00
interesting claim. I mean, this whole question
31:02
about the coincidences of numbers that
31:05
are sort of approximately this or
31:07
that, a famous one is e
31:09
to the power pie times square
31:12
root of 163, I think. That
31:14
number is really close to being
31:16
an integer. It doesn't have to
31:18
be. Could be any number, but
31:20
it's very close. It's, you know,
31:22
something. 99, 99, 99, 99. Many
31:24
times. Is that significant?
31:26
It turns out this mathematician named
31:29
Ramanujan, who was working in the
31:31
early part of the 20th century,
31:33
kind of noticed this and realized
31:36
that it was significant and in
31:38
fact built the whole theory based
31:40
on it, which among other things
31:42
is one of the main ways
31:44
that people compute the digits of
31:46
pie is using Ramanujan's theory that
31:48
came from kind of noticing this
31:50
kind of numerical coincidence. that E
31:52
to the pie square of 163,
31:55
I think that's the right one,
31:57
is close to an integer. You
31:59
know, I will... say that this thing about
32:01
you generate numbers and then you
32:03
say what are these numbers where do
32:06
they come from that's something
32:08
that as a you know when I do research
32:10
on things which I do all
32:12
the time but you know I'll
32:14
generate sequences of numbers and there's
32:16
a function and more from
32:19
language fine sequence function
32:21
which attempts to find
32:23
what function describes that sequence
32:25
of numbers and quite often it's useful.
32:27
I kind of say, yeah, I should
32:30
have been able to figure out why
32:32
these numbers are, you know, powers of
32:34
three minus powers of two or something.
32:37
But it notices, and I didn't, so
32:39
to speak. There's an online
32:41
system, OEIS, the online
32:43
encyclopedia of integer sequences,
32:45
built by a chap called Neil
32:47
Sloan, he started in the 1960s,
32:50
on index cards, and then a
32:52
book, and so on, collecting integer
32:54
sequences. And it's like, what is
32:56
the sequence? Oh, it's the number
32:58
of ways that you can assemble
33:00
sort of squares together and get
33:03
patterns that are distinct when you
33:05
rotate them around, or it's the
33:07
number ways that you can assemble
33:09
a tree with up to some
33:11
number of nodes and so on.
33:13
But it's quite often the case
33:16
that sort of you get, you generate
33:18
this from some completely
33:20
different method, then you might. you
33:23
just find sequence function, you might look it
33:25
up in OAIS, and it'll tell you, oh,
33:27
by the way, that's the number of trees,
33:29
you know, as a function of
33:31
that, the number of nodes or
33:33
something. And that's a useful thing.
33:35
That sort of mathematical coincidence is
33:38
useful. I would say that it's much
33:40
more, that has been much more successful
33:42
than the case of applying this to
33:44
the natural world. There is sort of
33:46
another case of this, which is
33:48
sort of an archaeology. and so
33:50
on, where people say, oh, the
33:52
height of the great pyramid divided
33:54
by the size of the nose of the
33:56
sphinx is, you know, very close
33:59
to pie square. something. That must
34:01
have been significant. Usually, the truth
34:03
is, those things were not significant
34:05
and nobody knew that that was
34:07
what was going on at the
34:10
time when the thing was being
34:12
built. But it is the case
34:14
that there was quite a tradition
34:16
of sort of hidden information, I
34:18
would say, particularly in the, well,
34:20
early printing, you know, 1500, 1600s,
34:23
and so on, of kind of
34:25
like hiding. kind of messages in
34:27
the weird numbers that would show
34:29
up in places. There's a whole
34:31
kind of tradition of that in
34:33
the the Kabala sort of Jewish
34:36
tradition is a lot about sort
34:38
of noticing weird numerical coincidences from
34:40
the from the Old Testament and
34:42
such like. And you know, did
34:44
the people who were writing this
34:46
were they sort of hiding a
34:49
secret message in the number of
34:51
Hebrew characters between here and there?
34:53
or is that just a coincidence?
34:55
That's the question. That's always a,
34:57
it's always a difficult question. Once
34:59
you have a thing to know
35:02
was that thing made for a
35:04
purpose or not is a very
35:06
difficult problem. I mean, it's, you
35:08
know, famously things like, well, famous
35:10
statement from the philosopher Emmanuel Kant,
35:12
if you see a hexagon drawn
35:15
in the sand, you can reasonably
35:17
assume that it was made for
35:19
a purpose by an intelligence of
35:21
some kind. That goes a certain
35:23
distance until you discover that there
35:26
are wind-produced kind of patterns in
35:28
the sand which can be hexagons,
35:30
but it's just the wind. And
35:32
unless you think of the wind
35:34
as an intelligence, which perhaps you
35:36
should, it's certainly not an intelligence
35:39
of the humankind. And even more
35:41
dramatically, if you look at the
35:43
North Pole of the planet Saturn,
35:45
it has a giant storm that
35:47
is a pretty good approximation to
35:49
a hexagon. So it's like on
35:52
the North Pole of Saturn, there's
35:54
a hexagon right there. And so
35:56
in Emmanuel Kant's heuristic, for... was
35:58
it made for a purpose? Was
36:00
it made by an intelligence? Saturn
36:02
was made by an intelligence, which
36:05
is sort of an interesting conclusion,
36:07
but it kind of, it talks
36:09
about the difficulty of recognizing what's
36:11
intelligent and what's merely the natural
36:13
world doing its thing. I mean,
36:15
another famous example from the beginning
36:18
of the 20th century was both
36:20
Marconi and, well, Tesla. had noticed
36:22
that if you just put a
36:24
radio mask up, there wasn't a
36:26
lot of radio transmission going on
36:28
in the world at that time,
36:31
and just put a radio mask
36:33
up, like in the middle of
36:35
the Atlantic, if you were on
36:37
a yacht going across the Atlantic
36:39
or something, you would hear all
36:41
kinds of radio emissions. What were
36:44
they? Tesla said there must be
36:46
the Martian signal link. Marconi didn't
36:48
know what they were. But what
36:50
they actually are, are particular... magnetohedodynamic
36:52
effects in the Earth's ionosphere and
36:54
they are essentially a pure piece
36:57
of nature but yet they make
36:59
these sounds that you might think
37:01
were of kind of intelligent origin.
37:03
Now to confuse things even further,
37:05
days later, whale songs were discovered
37:08
and whale songs sounded awful a
37:10
lot like these kind of emissions
37:12
from the ionosphere. and the emissions
37:14
honestly radio, but if you play
37:16
them as sound, they sound a
37:18
lot like the sounds from whales
37:21
and so on. So it's very
37:23
confusing. You know, the whales are
37:25
sort of intelligence like us. We
37:27
think the honest for us is
37:29
not an intelligence like us, but
37:31
can we tell what was for
37:34
a purpose and what wasn't? And
37:36
it's the same kind of thing
37:38
when we're looking at a hinge
37:40
or something and we're saying, you
37:42
know, was it set up in
37:44
this way? were the equinox or
37:47
was it set up this way
37:49
just because you know druid I
37:51
don't know what druid names would
37:53
have been druid Zestericks or something
37:55
was, I have no idea if
37:57
that's a valid druid name, but
38:00
I'm sort of remembering the the
38:02
asterisk series of comic books that
38:04
I think had had some druids
38:06
in it, so guessing it might
38:08
be something like that, although who
38:10
knows, but any case, we did
38:13
this druid or whatever, who decided
38:15
what Stonehenge should look like, were
38:17
they thinking about astronomy and the
38:19
equinox and so on, or were
38:21
they just like, oh, put it
38:23
this way, and it's hard to
38:26
know. And sometimes, you know, in
38:28
some of these cases, when it
38:30
says, yes, it's very accurately aligned,
38:32
so that it, you know, so
38:34
the light falls on exactly this
38:37
stone at the time of the
38:39
equinox or whatever, and then it's
38:41
like, well, how accurately is it
38:43
aligned that way? And, you know,
38:45
maybe they meant it to be
38:47
for the equinox, but they didn't
38:50
know their astronomy well enough, and
38:52
so it isn't quite aligned. So
38:54
it's always very difficult to tell.
38:58
Rebot comments, atmospheric noise is about
39:00
as random as we can get,
39:03
I think. Well, actually, the thing
39:05
I was just telling about the
39:07
atmosphere is a little bit of
39:10
a, giving a bit of a
39:12
twist to that. I think, you
39:15
know, the wind and kind of
39:17
turbulence in the atmosphere is pretty
39:19
random in some sense, but there's
39:22
definite regularity to it. For example,
39:24
the very fact that wind has
39:26
gusts is a piece of regularity
39:29
that, I mean, why does wind
39:31
have gusts? It's because, well, in
39:34
the end, motion of fluids is
39:36
sometimes motion of fluids is very
39:38
smooth. That's so-called laminar flow when
39:41
the fluid just sort of slides
39:43
past an obstacle. But when the
39:45
fluid is going faster, it's going
39:48
faster, it's going faster. produces turbulence
39:50
and turbulence. You can think of
39:53
it as it's making all these
39:55
little eddies of air or water
39:57
if it's if it's water that
40:00
one's dealing with and there's a
40:02
sort of a general cascade that
40:04
happens when you start with a
40:07
big eddy it gets ground down
40:09
to small and small and small
40:12
eddies and eventually the eddies kind
40:14
of dissipate away but that cascade
40:16
of eddies is from the big
40:19
to the small as kind of
40:21
a somewhat accurate universal law that
40:23
the the energy of the of
40:26
a certain eddy as a e
40:28
to the minus 5 thirds law,
40:31
or k to the minus 5
40:33
thirds actually, no, that's in that,
40:35
sorry, that's the wave number, the
40:38
size of the eddies varies like
40:40
the minus 5 thirds power of
40:43
their size. And that sort of,
40:45
the reason for the gusting has
40:47
to do with that kind of
40:50
cascade of eddies sizes and so
40:52
on. It's one of these things
40:54
where when you look at it
40:57
on a small enough scale, if
40:59
you look at the individual molecules,
41:02
you'll be like, yeah, they're pretty
41:04
random. Now, of course, if you
41:06
roll the clock back and you
41:09
say, well, how did the molecules
41:11
start off? In principle, you can
41:13
do the computation to work out
41:16
where the molecules will be. It's
41:18
sort of a big story that
41:21
I've tried to clarify, actually, in
41:23
recent years that this phenomenon of
41:25
computational irreducibility tells one, well, well,
41:28
But in practice, it will take
41:30
you a computation far beyond any
41:32
computation you can do to figure
41:35
that out. So for practical purposes,
41:37
you can't know whether the molecules
41:40
are going to be, and you
41:42
just have to say, well, they
41:44
seem random, because there's nothing we
41:47
can say that can predict where
41:49
they'll be. All right, let me
41:51
see. Other kinds of questions. Here's
41:55
a question that might be
41:57
reasonably simple from ego. The
42:00
question is, how does
42:02
IBM Watson AI stand
42:05
against modern LLLMs? Well,
42:07
so for those who remember
42:09
it, IBM Watson was
42:12
a system that was put
42:14
up in 2009 or 2010,
42:16
and it was kind of
42:19
a publicity stunt. So
42:21
IBM had for many, many
42:23
years worked on text
42:26
retrieval, which is the problem
42:28
of you've got a big
42:30
piece of text online, you want to
42:33
find these words from that piece
42:35
of text that would be just
42:37
searching for the keywords, you want
42:39
to kind of say, well, where is
42:41
there something in my text that's
42:44
similar to this sentence that I'm
42:46
typing in? And the fact that
42:48
you have a lot of sentences which
42:50
have the in them. just like the
42:53
sentence you typed in has a V
42:55
in it, that's not terribly significant. So
42:57
there are a bunch of different ways
42:59
to find out, well, what is the,
43:01
what is a relevant match? What is
43:03
a significant match? What's not a
43:05
significant match? There's a technique, actually
43:08
not a mentored IBM, but it
43:10
was sort of used there, a
43:12
thing called TFIDF, term frequency, inverse
43:14
document frequency, which essentially is the
43:17
thing that says, if there's a
43:19
really obscure word, you know, you
43:21
know, a a rhombic hexacontahedron, to
43:23
pick an obscure word. That happens
43:25
to be the name of the
43:27
three-dimensional solid that is our company
43:30
logo and so on. But it's
43:32
an obscure word, a rhombic hexacontahedron.
43:34
If your document somewhere in it
43:37
has the world hexacontahedron and
43:39
your search query has
43:41
hexacontahedron, the place where
43:43
you find hexacontahedron in
43:45
the document is probably
43:47
really significant. you what
43:49
you found in your query and what
43:52
you found the document is the word I
43:54
don't know significant let's say
43:56
that's less significant it's
43:58
the word the is
44:00
completely insignificant. So there are
44:02
these methods for figuring out what's
44:04
the relevant thing to pick out
44:07
of a document. So IBM had
44:09
worked on a bunch of these
44:11
techniques and then they kind of
44:13
wanted to have an IBM as
44:16
a company with a long history
44:18
of doing this to have sort
44:20
of a publicity stunt of You
44:22
know, can we show off all
44:25
this technology? I have to say,
44:27
I know quite a few of
44:29
the people who are involved in
44:31
this whole story. So I'll give
44:34
you just the external version of
44:36
this. The thing that, so somebody
44:38
figured out, well, what's, you know,
44:40
the Japanese game? Again, I don't
44:43
watch television, so I've not really
44:45
seen this, but I, it's kind
44:47
of like you have a bunch
44:49
of clues. and then you're kind
44:52
of asked, you know, given these
44:54
clues, you know, who does this
44:56
correspond to, you know, who's a,
44:58
who's a person, what's a, what's
45:01
a kind of animal that has
45:03
some pointing ears and a bushy
45:05
tail and climbs trees and this
45:07
and that and the other, and
45:10
it's sort of, is it a,
45:12
I don't know what does that,
45:14
but that kind of thing. So.
45:16
The sort of publicity stunt was
45:19
to try to use text retrieval
45:21
methods to sort of beat the
45:23
game of Jeopardy and which is
45:26
a television TV game show. And
45:28
the idea was to use web
45:30
content and things like this and
45:32
essentially to do text retrieval searching
45:35
based on the clues that were
45:37
given in the Jeopardy game and
45:39
then surface the answers. So this
45:41
was done in a kind of
45:44
televised thing the one time I
45:46
watched Japanese on television. What was
45:48
quite interesting to see was that
45:50
at the bottom of the screen
45:53
they showed the runner-up kind of
45:55
possible answers. And that was very
45:57
revealing because it was revealing that
45:59
this... was the textatory or play
46:02
because some of those answers had
46:04
incorrect capitalization and things like this.
46:06
They were really coming from the
46:08
source document. It's like here's the
46:11
sentence that comes from the source
46:13
document that seems to be a
46:15
match. So anyway, they did that
46:17
the the the big thing was
46:20
that the the IBM machine that
46:22
was very dramatically presented as this
46:24
big physical machine, won against the
46:26
then reigning jeopardy champion. I think
46:29
in reality, part of the way
46:31
that that game works is do
46:33
you lock in a win or
46:35
do you try for the next
46:38
clue? And that's kind of a
46:40
probability estimates question. And humans are
46:42
really not very good at that.
46:44
Humans are always too hopeful. or
46:47
two pessimistic. And humans don't just
46:49
kind of coolly weigh the odds
46:51
and make their choices based on
46:53
those. Machines are much better at
46:56
that. And I think that's in
46:58
the end why the machine won.
47:00
It was more or less you
47:02
know the clues it was doing
47:05
sort of similarly, but it could
47:07
win on doing the probability estimates
47:09
correctly. So that was the story
47:11
of Watson came out soon after
47:14
the Wolfram Alpha. Well, if my
47:16
offer came out and it was,
47:18
it never really went too far.
47:20
It was, I think as a,
47:23
you know, as a piece of
47:25
corporate commentary, it's, it was sort
47:27
of a publicity stunt that got
47:29
people to pay attention to IBM.
47:32
I mean, they spent billions of
47:34
dollars advertising Watson as a way
47:36
to do for your corporate data,
47:38
what it had done for Japanese.
47:41
And to kind of find a
47:43
needle in a haystack. in sort
47:45
of corporate data or medical data
47:47
or something like this. you know,
47:50
find the needle in the haystack
47:52
and win big. The truth is,
47:54
in many ways, and this is
47:56
maybe more of a business statement,
47:59
it was sort of solving the
48:01
wrong problem because most companies have
48:03
their data in a pretty organized
48:05
form and databases and things like
48:08
that. It's all just rows of
48:10
numbers and so on. And the
48:12
problem ends up being, can you
48:14
answer a question that is maybe
48:17
stated just in plain English? answer
48:19
a question relative to all that
48:21
structured data. And actually that's the
48:23
technology we built in Wolfmalfa was
48:26
very suitable for that. It's been
48:28
used many many times for that.
48:30
And it's something for which this
48:32
text retrieval approach of Watson really
48:35
wasn't a good idea. There are
48:37
more there's more to this story
48:39
of our interactions with IBM and
48:41
Watson, but I don't think I
48:44
should at least not yet tell
48:46
that on a live stream. I
48:48
have to think about that. Maybe
48:50
in a few years from now,
48:53
maybe it's an interesting story, it's
48:55
an interesting story and maybe it
48:57
can be told. But in a
48:59
case, how does that relate to
49:02
a modern LLM? Well, the methodology
49:04
was different. As I said, it
49:06
was really about text retrieval, much
49:08
more like a search engine. In
49:11
fact, right after the Japanese win,
49:13
I tried, how well could you
49:15
do just with a search engine?
49:17
And the answer was pretty well.
49:20
The main issue with the search
49:22
engine was... that yes, you could
49:24
get the right answer on the
49:26
first search engine result page, but
49:29
knowing which of those answers from
49:31
the search engine result page was
49:33
the absolute winner, that was more
49:35
difficult. That final ranking was a
49:38
bit more difficult. But, okay, so
49:40
for an LMLM, LEM's work in
49:42
a rather different way. They are
49:44
taking the input text, might be
49:47
a huge amount, trillion tokens, whatever
49:49
it is, and they're really grinding
49:51
it up. They're getting trained to
49:53
replicate that text. That's their training
49:56
task. But the way that they
49:58
represent that text is really ground
50:00
down to all these numbers inside
50:02
the neural nets and so on.
50:05
There's no lump of text there
50:07
that says, you know, John Smith
50:09
or something as a potential answer.
50:11
It's the John Smith is encoded
50:14
in this way that nobody really
50:16
understands very well as all these
50:18
little detailed numbers that are part
50:21
of the neural net weights that
50:23
are part of the 100 billion
50:25
neural net weights, let's say. When it
50:27
will be interesting actually, and I
50:29
see an easy experiment, I'm sure
50:32
somebody's tried it, I don't know
50:34
the answer, of how well does
50:36
the modern LLLM do on the
50:38
original televised jeopardy competition
50:40
that Watson did? My guess is
50:42
that a modern LLLM will do very well
50:45
at that. My guess is that we'll pretty
50:47
much nail it. And almost effortlessly so.
50:49
I might be wrong, be a good
50:51
experiment to try, but that would be
50:53
my guess. But the way it's doing
50:55
it's doing it. is very different.
50:58
And even though the effect might
51:00
be, well, somewhat, somewhat the same.
51:02
But that's a thought on that. I
51:04
mean, it's a very different term.
51:06
These approaches are all very
51:08
different from what we're doing with
51:11
Wolfram Alpha or Wolfram language,
51:13
where we're actually computing answers.
51:16
In the text retrieval case,
51:18
you're literally pulling out that
51:20
piece of text. In the LLM case,
51:22
you're pulling out that sort
51:25
of statistical pattern. that you
51:27
learn from the pattern of a piece of
51:29
text. It's not, you are using essentially
51:32
an algorithm to compute the
51:34
answer, or you're using sort
51:36
of the structured, curated data
51:38
to be able to figure
51:40
out the answer. That's what
51:42
we're doing in Wolfram Language.
51:44
It's something where Wolfram Language
51:47
is a useful tool for humans.
51:49
It's also become a useful tool for AIs.
51:51
More and more of our customers now are
51:53
AIs. Presumably there's a human at the end
51:56
of the chain who's asking the AI to
51:58
do something and then the AI is
52:00
asking our technology to do something,
52:02
one assumes, maybe one day it'll
52:04
be AIs for themselves, so to
52:06
speak. But the dynamic is that
52:09
the the LLM is providing this
52:11
kind of linguistic interface to ultimately
52:13
this computation. So it's sort of
52:15
a hierarchy of things, from the
52:17
pure text retrieval to the kind
52:19
of statistical ground up thing to
52:21
the actual computation side of things.
52:24
Let's see. Okay, Opie comments, would
52:26
the LLLM have the same reaction
52:28
time to compete and press the
52:30
buzzer? That's an interesting question. That's
52:32
a good sort of, you know,
52:34
assessment of LLLM's because the fact
52:37
is that LLLM's, well, an LLLM,
52:39
the way it works, like chat
52:41
GPT, I think, had about 400
52:43
layers in the neural mat. And,
52:45
you know, you're kind of, you're,
52:47
you're sending that. data through those
52:49
layers and that takes a certain
52:52
amount of time and it has
52:54
to go through all those layers
52:56
for every token it produces every
52:58
piece of a word every word
53:00
every character whatever that it produces
53:02
now you know can one distill
53:05
the neural net so that it
53:07
has fewer layers can one have
53:09
faster hardware to run it on
53:11
those are all things one expects
53:13
to be possible and so they'll
53:15
speed up but it's a good
53:17
question at what point you reach
53:20
the jeopardy point so to given
53:22
the timing information. Oh, there's a
53:24
question here from Reebok. Is it
53:26
possible that one day will predict
53:28
the weather years in advance? I
53:30
think the answer is no. Plain
53:32
and simple. I think that there
53:35
are two different things. One is
53:37
the sort of computational irreducibility of
53:39
all that turbulence and all those
53:41
kinds of things. The other thing
53:43
is that in the end... you
53:45
need to know precisely the way
53:48
the world is set up and
53:50
precisely you know what tree is
53:52
growing on what hill and what,
53:54
you know, how much plankton is
53:56
there in this piece of the
53:58
ocean that causes this or that
54:00
thing. So to know, and even
54:03
in the case of predicting the
54:05
weather far in advance, you know,
54:07
how much traffic is they going
54:09
to be on this road that's
54:11
going to stir up the air
54:13
in this or that way? So
54:16
I think the sort of lack
54:18
of knowledge of the future of
54:20
the world kind of precludes that.
54:22
Now what level... of general prediction
54:24
can you make? This is kind
54:26
of one of the challenges of
54:28
climate work is, okay, the weather
54:31
is one thing. That is the
54:33
details of, you know, what will
54:35
the temperature be? Will it be
54:37
raining in this place or that?
54:39
Really hard to predict things about
54:41
clouds and when clouds form and
54:44
etc., etc., etc. Now if you
54:46
say, well, can I say something
54:48
about the weather a year from
54:50
now, it's very challenging. Because, you're
54:52
sort of, are there things that
54:54
you can say in generality and
54:56
approximately, versus things that you can
54:59
say as a matter of something
55:01
like weather prediction? The transition between
55:03
those things is really tricky, because
55:05
when you're predicting something, you know,
55:07
far in advance, you can't simulate
55:09
every single blade of grass for
55:11
sure not, but even, you know,
55:14
the size of the region on
55:16
the earth that you're simulating, I
55:18
don't know how big it is
55:20
these these days. I think it's
55:22
like 10 kilometers on a side,
55:24
something like that, is the grid
55:27
of kind of what you can
55:29
do very long term sort of
55:31
climate prediction from. It's a very,
55:33
a very coarse grid. So anything
55:35
that's happening that matters about, you
55:37
know, this particular cliff that has
55:39
this particular airflow and so on,
55:42
it's like you're out of luck.
55:44
It's just a 10 kilometer square
55:46
grid, grid section. And it's, it's
55:48
super hard to know what will
55:50
happen and you know there's one
55:52
thing is to do a computer
55:55
simulation the other thing to do
55:57
is to say, given this effect,
55:59
like increasing carbon dioxide levels, increasing
56:01
retention of water vapor in the
56:03
atmosphere, all these kinds of things.
56:05
Given these effects, can we make
56:07
a kind of physics understandable, human
56:10
understandable argument for why this or
56:12
that thing should happen? Sort of
56:14
two competing methodologies. One is the
56:16
kind of reason it through kind
56:18
of almost natural philosophy style, but
56:20
whether you and the other is
56:22
run the computer simulation, and hope
56:25
you've got all the parameters right
56:27
and just trust the answer. They're
56:29
both fraught with difficulty and you
56:31
know if you can if you
56:33
can kind of make them agree
56:35
and not cheat in doing that
56:38
then you have something going for
56:40
you but it's really hard and
56:42
I think the I mean my
56:44
observation has been that the closer
56:46
you get to people who actually
56:48
do climate modeling really on the
56:50
ground with computer systems, the more
56:53
they say, hey, we want to
56:55
just make these physics arguments, and
56:57
vice versa, so to speak. It's
56:59
a pretty difficult area to know,
57:01
sort of to be able to
57:03
say what's going to happen. But
57:06
that's kind of the story of,
57:08
and to know, you know, will
57:10
this happen three years from now,
57:12
there are some large scale atmospheric
57:14
effects like El Nino's and so
57:16
on, which have effects on timescales
57:18
of order a few years of
57:21
order a few years. Similarly, things
57:23
changing in ocean currents and so
57:25
on. And there there's some predictability
57:27
on multi-year timescales, usually with the
57:29
kind of physics argument type methodology,
57:31
not the detailed closer to weather
57:33
forecasting type argument. Reebelke is asking,
57:36
then it is whether a good
57:38
random sequence. Well, up to a
57:40
point, but you know, there is
57:42
some predictability. I mean, like if
57:44
you say the temperature... here is
57:46
random. Well, it's not really. In
57:49
the course of the year, you
57:51
know, in places inland, for example,
57:53
you have this essentially sinusoidal temperature
57:55
is a function of time through
57:57
the year. That's the overall temperature
57:59
profile. Now in detail day to
58:01
day there may be all kinds
58:04
of seemingly random fluctuations, but there's
58:06
still an overarching pattern to the
58:08
whole thing. Let's see, there's a
58:10
question here from Brianna, how do
58:12
you calculate wind speed if wind
58:14
is a pressure difference? So I
58:17
mean the easy way to generate
58:19
wind speed is to the an
58:21
animometer where you know it's been
58:23
the same forever and ever. It's
58:25
just this little thing you see
58:27
that's twirling around and has little
58:29
cups that catch the wind and
58:32
it gets twirled around at a
58:34
different speed depending on on how
58:36
fast the wind is going. That
58:38
works okay if you're dealing with
58:40
like you just stick it on
58:42
a pole and you're measuring it
58:45
at the surface. It's a bit
58:47
trickier to measure the wind speed
58:49
when you're you know, in the
58:51
air, because among other things, it's
58:53
like you don't have, you don't
58:55
have the pole that you're attaching
58:57
things to, to measure winds aloft
59:00
is a trickier thing. These days,
59:02
I guess, you know, it's some,
59:04
let's see how, I mean, clearly
59:06
you can have a balloon, if
59:08
you have a balloon and you
59:10
send the balloon up, the balloon
59:12
is going to get blown by
59:15
the wind, and you can just
59:17
watch the balloon and see how
59:19
fast it goes, and with modern
59:21
GPS, that's not difficult. I'm trying
59:23
to remember how this, I mean,
59:25
planes can, I'm trying to think,
59:28
it's sort of an application of
59:30
vectors, so to speak. The plane
59:32
thinks it's going in this direction,
59:34
but and it has a certain
59:36
thrust that it's pushing with, but
59:38
the wind is blowing it in
59:40
that direction, and it's sort of
59:43
the vector sum that determines what
59:45
the actual direction is. And I
59:47
think you can deduce... In fact,
59:49
yeah, I know you can deduce
59:51
something about the winds at different
59:53
altitudes by looking at what's happening
59:56
to planes. But the whole question
59:58
about is the wind, for example,
1:00:00
constant as you go up, no it
1:00:02
isn't at all. The wind is
1:00:04
going in very different directions as
1:00:07
you go as sort of as
1:00:09
you go up and winds at
1:00:12
high altitudes are routinely very fast.
1:00:14
I mean, there would be, you
1:00:16
know, if you're if you're
1:00:18
in a plane flying at,
1:00:20
you know, 36,000 feet, 40,000
1:00:22
feet or something, the winds
1:00:25
can routinely be 200 miles
1:00:27
an hour. And which at the
1:00:29
surface just doesn't happen that way.
1:00:31
I mean in general what's happening
1:00:33
is there's friction between the air
1:00:36
and the surface of the earth
1:00:38
and that that causes the the
1:00:40
air that's close to the surface
1:00:42
to be moving well in the
1:00:44
end it's moving very slowly at
1:00:47
the you know right down you
1:00:49
know an inch from the ground
1:00:51
or something and as you go
1:00:53
further up there's kind of that
1:00:55
sort of that effect becomes less
1:00:57
important than that it's just how
1:01:00
much is the air getting blown
1:01:02
around, so to speak. Let's
1:01:04
see. If the Earth started rotating
1:01:07
in reverse, ask Kuki, would
1:01:09
that have an effect on
1:01:11
the weather? Absolutely. I mean,
1:01:14
at the moment when
1:01:16
it started turning backwards,
1:01:18
you know, all hell will break
1:01:20
loose, but let's assume that
1:01:22
we just picked an Earth.
1:01:24
that was otherwise the same but
1:01:27
was rotating the other way around. The
1:01:29
point is that, let's see if I
1:01:31
remember which way around this goes.
1:01:33
Cyclones are in the northern
1:01:36
hemisphere, rotate in one direction
1:01:38
in the southern hemisphere, and
1:01:40
not remember, I think cyclones
1:01:42
go clockwise in the northern
1:01:44
hemisphere. So that's regions of
1:01:46
low pressure that have essentially
1:01:49
wind circulating around them.
1:01:51
They, because of the rotation of
1:01:53
the earth... those have the rotation of the
1:01:55
earth leads to this sort of asymmetry
1:01:57
between what happens in the southern hammers.
1:01:59
in the northern hemisphere, at
1:02:02
least in the direction
1:02:04
of rotation of these
1:02:06
things. That's a result
1:02:08
of this thing called
1:02:10
the Coriolus force, which
1:02:12
is a force that, let's
1:02:14
see, it's a force that you
1:02:17
get on a rotating object.
1:02:19
It's roughly that if you,
1:02:21
well, yeah, let's let's give
1:02:24
an example, a practical
1:02:26
example. If people
1:02:28
are shooting. guns, artillery, and
1:02:31
they have a shell and they shoot it
1:02:33
20 miles. It goes up in
1:02:35
this parabolic trajectory more or
1:02:37
less than it comes down again.
1:02:39
And the question is, as that
1:02:41
happens, as the thing is going
1:02:43
through the air, so to speak,
1:02:45
the earth is turning underneath it.
1:02:47
And that effectively, as you work
1:02:50
out all the math and so
1:02:52
on, that ends up having an
1:02:54
effect on then where relative to
1:02:56
where the earth is. If you're
1:02:58
fixed, if you're in knowing if
1:03:01
what matters is where the shell
1:03:03
is going to fall, is it
1:03:05
going to fall, you know, on
1:03:07
that, you know, battalion
1:03:09
or that other one or something,
1:03:11
or on that, you know, where
1:03:14
is it going to fall, that's
1:03:16
that question of where
1:03:19
those troops are is fixed on the
1:03:21
surface of the earth. But where the
1:03:23
shell goes is... during the time the
1:03:26
shell is in the northern hemisphere and
1:03:28
the southern hemisphere. And so that you
1:03:30
can think of that as being like
1:03:32
a force if you if you fix
1:03:35
yourself to the coordinate system of
1:03:37
the folks on the ground, it's as
1:03:39
if there's a force that's pushing the
1:03:41
shell on a certain direction. And
1:03:43
that force, as you think about sort of
1:03:46
the coordinates of how you how
1:03:48
you define things, is in an opposite
1:03:50
direction in the northern hemisphere in
1:03:52
the southern hemisphere and the southern hemisphere.
1:03:55
And so, for example, when when people
1:03:57
have artillery tables back in the day
1:03:59
with and they were still kind
1:04:01
of, you know, to set a
1:04:04
gun or something, you had to
1:04:06
actually look up this table of
1:04:09
numbers. They had to have different
1:04:11
ones for the Northern Hemisphere and
1:04:13
the Southern Hemisphere. That effect
1:04:16
in a less troublesome
1:04:18
setting, perhaps, is what
1:04:20
leads to the different circulation
1:04:22
in the Northern Hemisphere and
1:04:25
the Southern Hemisphere of these
1:04:27
high pressure. cyclones and
1:04:30
so on. By the way, there's
1:04:32
a fun story of a long
1:04:34
time ago. There was a, perhaps
1:04:36
not so directly relevant,
1:04:39
but it's an interesting
1:04:41
story anyway. There was
1:04:43
a plane that a fighter plane,
1:04:46
I think, that was sort
1:04:48
of electronically controlled fighter
1:04:50
plane. This was
1:04:52
in the 80s, I guess. And
1:04:54
one feature that it had was,
1:04:57
it had had was, verified
1:04:59
the code for this plane and it's
1:05:01
correct. Of course, what does it
1:05:03
mean for the code for a fighter
1:05:05
plane to be correct? Because it
1:05:07
depends what you want the fighter
1:05:09
plane to do. And the thing that happened
1:05:12
was the fighter plane was being
1:05:14
tested and it flew over the
1:05:16
equator to the southern hemisphere and
1:05:19
it turned upside down. And that,
1:05:21
and now, is that correct? Is
1:05:23
that not correct? You probably don't
1:05:25
want the plane to fly upside
1:05:27
down. But... That was a thing
1:05:29
I think it had to do
1:05:31
with correcting for the Coriolus force,
1:05:33
I'm not sure, but that was
1:05:35
a sort of an interesting case
1:05:37
of you think you've defined what
1:05:39
it means to be correct, but unless
1:05:42
you've thought of all the things
1:05:44
that could happen, it's very hard
1:05:46
to imagine what it means to
1:05:48
be correct, so to speak. And
1:05:50
that was a case where rather
1:05:52
dramatically it was not what you
1:05:54
would have hoped it would do, so to
1:05:56
speak. Let's see. Um,
1:05:59
oh. So I see there was
1:06:01
a question here, let's see, just as
1:06:03
asking, what would it take to
1:06:05
stabilize the weather, like using
1:06:08
wind farms in reverse or
1:06:10
controlling ground albedo so that
1:06:12
we know it exactly? That's
1:06:14
a good question. I mean, this is
1:06:17
the whole area of geoengineering,
1:06:19
which is, you know, if we don't like
1:06:21
the way the climate is going,
1:06:23
how about we engineer it to
1:06:26
be something different? And we might
1:06:28
not like it because we feel bad
1:06:30
about the fact that we humans are
1:06:32
having an effect on it. We might
1:06:34
not like it because it's causing some
1:06:36
part of the earth to turn into a
1:06:38
desert. You know, we might not like
1:06:40
it for all kinds of reasons. But
1:06:42
let's just say we could turn the thermostat
1:06:44
of the earth and say this is what
1:06:47
the weather is going to be like.
1:06:49
It's of course a very complicated
1:06:51
question if one had that capability
1:06:53
and it was global. Where should
1:06:55
we set the temperature to be? Do we
1:06:58
want it to be the case that, you
1:07:00
know, Northern Canada is a great place for
1:07:02
growing bananas or something? Perhaps not. Perhaps
1:07:04
we say that's too far off. Do we
1:07:06
want it to be the case that doesn't
1:07:08
get quite as cold in the winter on
1:07:10
the east coast of the US or something?
1:07:13
Or do we want it to be the
1:07:15
case? You know, there are lots of different
1:07:17
things. It's very hard to decide what you
1:07:19
would want to do if you could just
1:07:21
control the thermostomat of the earth. It would
1:07:23
be much easier if you could
1:07:25
say, for, you know, this county
1:07:28
wants to pick this or that
1:07:30
thing to happen, that I think
1:07:32
is a more plausible, very difficult
1:07:34
to achieve, but a more sort
1:07:36
of socio- politically achievable kind of
1:07:38
objective. But in any case, this
1:07:40
question of can we in fact make
1:07:42
control these things, the answer is
1:07:44
almost certainly yes. There are all
1:07:47
kinds of different approaches, a,
1:07:49
well, I mean, to list a few of few
1:07:51
of them. And sometimes you hear about
1:07:53
these approaches and then I'll hear about them
1:07:55
from people and then a few years we'll
1:07:57
pass and I'll say well what what happened?
1:07:59
to that approach. And I say, well, it
1:08:02
doesn't work because of this and that
1:08:04
and the other thing. But a few
1:08:06
approaches are you put aerosols, little
1:08:08
particles in the upper atmosphere
1:08:10
of the Earth, it changes the albedo,
1:08:13
the amounts of sunlight that the Earth
1:08:15
reflects, as opposed to getting absorbed on
1:08:17
the surface. That means that the sky
1:08:20
will be a little bit dimmer, but it
1:08:22
means that less sunlight will reach the
1:08:24
Earth, and so you'll cool the
1:08:26
Earth. That's an example of an
1:08:28
approach. Another approach is... to seed the
1:08:30
oceans with iron so that you grow
1:08:33
more algae and those algae will will
1:08:35
ingest carbon dioxide. It's very
1:08:37
much like what plants do
1:08:39
in the, you know, plants. If
1:08:42
you plant more trees, you know,
1:08:44
there are a couple of trillion
1:08:46
trees on the earth right now.
1:08:48
If you planted another trillion trees,
1:08:50
you would have some effect as
1:08:53
well. It might be easier to
1:08:55
seed the oceans, kind of fertilize
1:08:57
the oceans and get the algae
1:08:59
in the oceans to do this.
1:09:01
That changes carbon dioxide levels. It's
1:09:03
not clear that the albedo change
1:09:06
is mostly to do with retention
1:09:08
of water vapor. So it's a
1:09:10
slightly less direct thing, but
1:09:12
it's presumably related.
1:09:14
Then there approaches, let's
1:09:16
see, there are all kinds of
1:09:18
approaches. What are some other ones?
1:09:21
There are the artificial
1:09:23
trees. That's another approach.
1:09:25
You know, controlling the wind.
1:09:27
You know, the fact that wind
1:09:30
farms work insofar as they
1:09:32
do is and they're tricky
1:09:34
business because wind farms
1:09:36
are very expensive, very
1:09:38
hard to maintain giant
1:09:40
pieces of equipment that, you
1:09:43
know, it's not clear that
1:09:45
the economics are complicated. But
1:09:48
insofar as it's not people
1:09:50
don't usually say, oh, there's
1:09:52
a wind farm there, so it took all
1:09:54
my wind, so to so to speak. There
1:09:57
is some of that, but that's a very
1:09:59
small effect. the amount that's removed
1:10:01
from the circulation of
1:10:03
the atmosphere is absolutely
1:10:05
tiny. I mean, it's the same thing as
1:10:08
you could say if we're using hydroelectric
1:10:10
power and we're doing things like,
1:10:12
you know, for example, we're storing
1:10:14
energy by pumping water up to
1:10:17
a higher level and then letting
1:10:19
it cascade down to a lower
1:10:21
level, in a sense that pumping act
1:10:24
is is doing something that that
1:10:26
is, well, let's see is that. Well, no,
1:10:28
if you're harvesting energy from the
1:10:30
tides, for example, I think that
1:10:32
pumping thing does it as well,
1:10:34
but to a smaller extent, if
1:10:36
you're taking energy from the tides,
1:10:39
you are effectively reducing the tides
1:10:41
of the earth, and ultimately you
1:10:43
will affect the rotation rate of the
1:10:45
earth. But that effect is so
1:10:47
absolutely infinitesimal that all the power
1:10:49
us humans could ever want would
1:10:51
not have a big effect on the rotation
1:10:54
of the earth. I think the question of,
1:10:56
you know, could you do something that
1:10:58
has a climate effect by using,
1:11:00
and so on, is because, but
1:11:02
that's mostly due to things like
1:11:04
earthquakes and so on. It's things
1:11:07
beyond what us humans, you know,
1:11:09
the levels of energy that us
1:11:11
humans can make use of. But I
1:11:13
think in the question of, you know,
1:11:15
could you do something that has a
1:11:17
climate effect by using sort of
1:11:20
wind farm level technology? I kind
1:11:22
of suspect the answer is no.
1:11:24
I kind of suspect that it's
1:11:26
just way too weak to have any
1:11:29
effect there. I think that a
1:11:31
sort of intermediate case is cloud
1:11:33
seeding. This question of whether
1:11:36
you can make clouds form,
1:11:38
make clouds rain, that's been
1:11:40
a thing that people have tried
1:11:42
for a hundred years. It's typical,
1:11:45
it's the one of the
1:11:47
things that is generally believed
1:11:49
to be true, is that sort
1:11:51
of every raindrop. was nucleated by
1:11:53
something like a piece of dust
1:11:55
or something, that when you have
1:11:58
water vapor in a cloud... It's
1:12:00
just going to stay as water vapor
1:12:02
unless something kind of reminds it that
1:12:04
it could all be clumping together.
1:12:06
And then at the right humidity level
1:12:09
and so on, right temperature level, it
1:12:11
will start to clump typically around that
1:12:13
nucleation site, which might be a
1:12:15
piece of dust might even perhaps
1:12:17
be to do with cosmic rays
1:12:19
and ionization in the atmosphere, things
1:12:22
like this. It's not clear whether
1:12:24
that's important. It's not clear whether
1:12:26
it may be the path of
1:12:28
lightning is determined by that as
1:12:30
well. the idea is, so the
1:12:32
idea is, let's put sort of
1:12:34
artificial nucleation sites into a cloud
1:12:36
and make it nucleate more
1:12:38
quickly and then rain. And Silver
1:12:41
Ride, I guess, is one of
1:12:43
the common substances used, I think.
1:12:45
But the basic point is, you're
1:12:47
sort of trailing behind a
1:12:49
plane, you've got a plane
1:12:51
flying around, and it's splirting
1:12:53
out stuff into a cloud,
1:12:55
and then the idea is...
1:12:57
for that to form the
1:12:59
nucleation sites that cause the
1:13:02
water vapor to form into
1:13:04
droplets and then drop as rain.
1:13:06
And people have been trying
1:13:08
to do this for 100 years. And
1:13:10
there have been some claimed, there
1:13:13
have been a bunch of claimed
1:13:15
successes, a bunch of, I guess, the, I
1:13:17
think an Olympics in Beijing a
1:13:19
few years ago, there was a
1:13:22
claim that cloud seeding had
1:13:24
been successful there are, there's
1:13:26
a company I know that's, well one of
1:13:28
the challenges of cloud seeding is were
1:13:30
you actually successful or was it going
1:13:32
to rain anyway? It's kind of like
1:13:34
one of these medical tests type things,
1:13:37
you know, if you didn't take the
1:13:39
drug would you have gotten better anyway?
1:13:41
And so it's sort of a challenge
1:13:43
to be able to figure out, you
1:13:45
know, what would have happened anyway, so
1:13:47
to speak? And one's getting better at
1:13:49
that because weather radar and once
1:13:51
able to sort of more accurately say
1:13:53
these were the droplets and this cloud
1:13:56
And another thing you can do is
1:13:58
just have your plane flying. a pattern
1:14:00
and if it rains in a pattern
1:14:02
that spells out a word, which I
1:14:05
don't think anybody has quite achieved yet,
1:14:07
but if it did that, if the
1:14:09
pattern of the rain as seen by
1:14:12
a plane or a satellite or something
1:14:14
was spelling out the word hello or
1:14:16
something, you would be, that would be
1:14:19
a pretty convincing argument that It was
1:14:21
really, you know, the clouds are not
1:14:23
kind of spontaneously rain in the pattern
1:14:26
of the word hello. So you probably
1:14:28
really did succeed in doing cloud
1:14:30
seeding. But that's sort of
1:14:32
an intermediate case of local,
1:14:34
in a sense, local climate.
1:14:36
It's still been very challenging
1:14:39
to make that work. Let's see. Well,
1:14:41
Jogan is commenting, oh gosh,
1:14:43
got a couple of comments in
1:14:45
that should go up on my way
1:14:48
here, but Jillian is is asking
1:14:50
can the Earth's tilt
1:14:52
ever be affected?
1:14:54
What changes would
1:14:56
this cause? So the
1:14:58
Earth is tilted at
1:15:01
23 degrees relative
1:15:03
to the plane in which
1:15:05
it orbits the sun.
1:15:08
That's the... Oh my gosh.
1:15:10
That tilt is... What is
1:15:12
that? The obliquity,
1:15:14
I think of the Earth. I
1:15:17
think that's right. I
1:15:19
mean, most of the planets rotate
1:15:21
around in more or less the
1:15:23
same plane as they orbit the
1:15:26
sun. Famously, Uranus is tipped the
1:15:28
other way and rotates backwards, but
1:15:30
mostly it's close. The Earth is
1:15:33
23 degrees away. That's what leads
1:15:35
to the seasons is the fact
1:15:38
that that the Earth is not
1:15:40
rotating one with the amount of
1:15:42
sunlight you get depends
1:15:44
on a different times of
1:15:47
the year depends on. on
1:15:49
where you, depends on, on,
1:15:52
it varies because of
1:15:54
that tilt. There is a,
1:15:56
there is a, the, the,
1:15:59
the earth. It's its axis
1:16:01
processes around every 23,000 years,
1:16:03
I think. And so the
1:16:05
this this question of kind
1:16:07
of so so it's tilt is it's
1:16:09
like a top that's if you if
1:16:12
you watch a top before it
1:16:14
topples over, you'll see it
1:16:16
process the axis of rotation
1:16:18
will make this little circle.
1:16:20
The the axis of the earth
1:16:23
is doing the same thing every
1:16:25
23,000 years or so. But in
1:16:27
terms of. of things that affect the
1:16:29
tilt of the earth, I'm not
1:16:31
sure that much does. I mean,
1:16:33
and ultimately, you know, the moon
1:16:35
is very tied into what's happening
1:16:37
with the earth, and I don't know,
1:16:40
the moon is gradually receding from
1:16:42
the earth, and I don't know
1:16:44
whether when the moon has receded
1:16:46
far from the earth, or in
1:16:48
earlier times when the moon was
1:16:50
closer to the earth, I don't know
1:16:52
what that will have done to the, to
1:16:54
the tilt of the earth. Joggen comments,
1:16:57
there's a large difference between what
1:16:59
an ideal climate would be and what
1:17:01
changes would mean trouble for us
1:17:03
given our current infrastructure. Yes, absolutely.
1:17:05
I have no idea what an ideal
1:17:07
climate would be. I think it will
1:17:09
be dependent. The 8 billion people on
1:17:11
the earth would probably all have different
1:17:13
opinions about that. You know, the thing that
1:17:15
is probably the most difficult aspect
1:17:18
of climate change is that, you know,
1:17:20
we have an infrastructure that in...
1:17:22
recent years has been built up to
1:17:24
a high degree of precision, so to
1:17:26
speak. I mean, you know, a thousand years
1:17:28
ago, the climate changed the bunch
1:17:30
of times. You know, in the
1:17:32
1600s, it was much colder in
1:17:34
the middle of the 1600s, still
1:17:36
not clear quite why, the so-called
1:17:38
mourned minimum, that might have had
1:17:40
something to do with the output
1:17:42
from the sun. It's not really
1:17:44
clear, but it was much colder
1:17:46
then. and you know and there were
1:17:49
times when you know different parts of
1:17:51
the earth were very fertile versus not
1:17:53
and so on and you know in
1:17:55
past times over the course of a
1:17:57
hundred years people would just move their
1:17:59
sheep from one place to another, and
1:18:01
it wasn't sort of a big deal.
1:18:03
But in modern times, you know, we've
1:18:05
built up a lot of, you know,
1:18:08
we've built our condos on the beach
1:18:10
type thing, and we've built up a
1:18:12
lot of detailed things that depend
1:18:14
on the climate, the sea level,
1:18:16
and so on being the way that
1:18:18
they are right now. And, you know, that's,
1:18:20
I think, one of the challenges, which
1:18:23
at some level, as an economic challenge,
1:18:25
at some level, you know, people... people
1:18:27
have built up things the way they
1:18:29
want them to be and don't want
1:18:32
them to change type thing. But I
1:18:34
think that's, it's absolutely true that
1:18:36
the, you know, the number one issue
1:18:38
is the effect on modern infrastructure. And
1:18:41
even things like, you know, questions of,
1:18:43
you know, how much is that piece
1:18:45
of land worth? If you can grow
1:18:48
crops on it, it's worth more than
1:18:50
if it's just random, you know, tundra
1:18:52
that you don't seem to be able
1:18:55
to do much with. But I think,
1:18:57
so yes, that's, that's, and that's, you
1:18:59
know, that's the challenge is to
1:19:02
unravel kind of, sort of,
1:19:04
I don't know, economic
1:19:06
effects from kind of
1:19:09
the actual sort of
1:19:11
physics of climate. And
1:19:13
then, you know, I think
1:19:15
there's a certain kind of
1:19:18
ethical view that, you know,
1:19:20
the earth has been going along
1:19:22
just fine. and we shouldn't, you
1:19:25
know, we shouldn't affect it. That's more
1:19:27
of, I think, an ethical kind of
1:19:29
statement that it's unclear what that, you
1:19:31
know, from an ethics point of view,
1:19:34
that's a complicated story, because it's like,
1:19:36
you know, we got 8 billion people
1:19:38
and, you know, we think ethics is
1:19:40
really a pretty human thing, and it's
1:19:42
sort of more important in a sense,
1:19:44
in ethics as we do it, normally
1:19:46
as humans, because humans is really only
1:19:49
defined relative to humans, the ethics of
1:19:51
a very hard to very hard to
1:19:53
define. what we mean by you know
1:19:55
what should we what should we do
1:19:57
relative to the rock what should the
1:19:59
rock be doing, so to speak, that's
1:20:01
not really a, you know, ethics as
1:20:04
a human story. And so when
1:20:06
it's a question of sort of
1:20:08
ethics of the ethics of the
1:20:11
inanimate earth, that's a complicated story.
1:20:13
And that maybe is a is
1:20:15
a good thing to leave for
1:20:17
another time. Not that I know
1:20:20
how to unravel that question, but
1:20:22
that's, you know, that's a different
1:20:24
kind of overlay is some, the, is
1:20:27
what of what's going on and
1:20:29
sort of how to think about,
1:20:31
you know, the sort of the
1:20:33
theory of whether we should or
1:20:35
shouldn't be doing things to the
1:20:37
earth. And, you know, if we were
1:20:40
in a position to do, let's say,
1:20:42
we realize that it was going
1:20:44
to be a big win to
1:20:46
change the seasons. We, you know,
1:20:49
let's imagine in, you know, in
1:20:51
science fiction stories that, you know,
1:20:53
put engines, rocket engines on the
1:20:56
earth. And, you know, let's say we could
1:20:58
do that, which we cannot. It's far
1:21:00
far away from being possible. But let's
1:21:02
say we could, and we could change
1:21:04
the tilt of the earth and make
1:21:06
it be the case that we no
1:21:08
longer had seasons. You know, there's a
1:21:10
whole complicated question of what that would
1:21:12
mean and whether how we should think
1:21:14
about that ethically and otherwise. And spare
1:21:16
parts comments, even the weather can't agree
1:21:19
on what the weather should be. Yes,
1:21:21
and maybe that's a good place to end
1:21:23
for today. But thank you for asking
1:21:25
a lot of interesting questions. Get
1:21:27
me to think about a lot of
1:21:30
different things and well, thanks for asking
1:21:32
these questions and for joining me
1:21:34
and see you another time. Bye
1:21:37
for now. You've been listening to
1:21:39
the Stephen Wolfram podcast. You can
1:21:41
view the full Q&A series on
1:21:44
the Wolfram Research YouTube channel. For
1:21:46
more information on Stephen's publications, live
1:21:49
coding streams and this podcast, visit
1:21:51
Stephen Wolfram.com.
Podchaser is the ultimate destination for podcast data, search, and discovery. Learn More